rjohara.net |
Darwin-L Message Log 1:173 (September 1993)
Academic Discussion on the History and Theory of the Historical Sciences
This is one message from the Archives of Darwin-L (1993–1997), a professional discussion group on the history and theory of the historical sciences.
Note: Additional publications on evolution and the historical sciences by the Darwin-L list owner are available on SSRN.
<1:173>From DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Sat Sep 18 16:50:25 1993 Date: Sat, 18 Sep 1993 17:21:06 -0400 (EDT) From: DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Subject: Phylogeny (history) is important, classification is not To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Organization: University of NC at Greensboro We have had much discussion of classification. Along with many other people in evolutionary biology today, I don't find the topic of classification to be a fruitful one, and I would like to make the strong claim that classification is almost completely irrelevant to the contemporary practice of evolutionary biology. This is because much discussion of "classification" in fact fails to make a very important distinction now made within evolutionary biology between two different activities: (1) classifying (making groups), and (2) reconstructing phylogeny (evolutionary history). Until this distinction is clearly made there really can't be any fruitful discussion of either classification or phylogeny. This whole subject has been _enormously_ clarified in the last 15 years or so, and all practicioners in the field now make this distinction clearly. Here's a sketch of my reading of the situation; I'm sure my views are not universally held in all their details, but neither are they unique. Every paragraph below could easily be given monographic treatment, and many have been; my aim here is just to give a broad sketch for those who have an interest in the subject but have not followed the literature closely. We have among our members some leading historians of systematics and some leading systematists, so I apologize if I do violence to any of their views in the interest of brevity. While my comments address evolutionary biology, I like to think they have implications for historical linguistics and stemmatics as well. The last 25 years has seen an enormous growth in the study of phylogeny, the evolutionary history of life. This was one of the great fields of study in the late 1800s, but for much of the early and mid-20th century phylogeny was comparatively negleced in favor of studies of evolutionary mechanisms and "species-level" problems. (This species-level work was enormously important of course, and it is still with us.) Since the mid 1960s, however, interest in phylogeny has grown enormously due to three factors: (1) the development of computational methods for dealing with large quantities of data; (2) the availability of data on comparative molecular anatomy, though this has not been as important to the conceptual development of the phylogenetics revolution as the popular press (and some molecular biologists) would have people believe; and most importantly (3) a new conceptual understanding of the relationship between the observed similarities and differences among organisms and the histories that can be inferred from those similarities and differences. This last factor is behind the method of "cladistic analysis" which has effected a revolution in the study of phylogeny, and which is now the standard method for reconstructing evolutionary history. The conceptual development of cladistic analysis in the last 30 years or so has been as important to systematics as the development of the law of superposition -- that upper strata are younger than lower ones -- was long ago to geology. The briefest sketch of the long view of this subject would go like this (many of these statements could be qualified; there is an increasing body of published literature on this). Beginning in the 1600s and 1700s there was an enormous increase in factual knowledge of natural diversity on the part of European scientists. The notion of a linear "chain of being" which had been the principal organizing system for diversity up until that time came, as a consequence, to be challenged in the late 1700s and early 1800s, and a variety of other arrangements were conceived for the diversity of life, including maps, stars, circles, nets, and trees. Notice that I spoke here of _arrangements_. It is entirely true that may students of diversity engaged in classification and published classifications. But many theorists even during this early period argued that "classification" was not the right intellectual model for understanding and representing the structure of living diversity. In simplest terms, classifications are based on group-within-group relations; _arrangements_ may be based on group-within-group relations but also on some sort of positional relations in an abstract space: taxa are not only contained within other taxa, they are also near and far, between, above or below other taxa. Think of the difference between a printed listing of states, counties, and cities (group-within-group), and contrast that with a map of those same places showing their positions in geographical space. The chain of being is an example of a linear _arrangement_; it is not strictly speaking a classification because it contains a linear axis along which taxa must be placed. The term "system" was often used as a synonym of "arrangement", and people came to speak of "the natural system" -- that is, the true arrangement of the diversity of life. From this notion of system we derive the term "systematics" which is used for the field today. Many important workers in the early 1800s directly contrasted classifications (which they regard as inferior) with systems/arrangements, among them Macleay and Alfred Russel Wallace. One sometimes hears people say "a natural system of classification", but to the workers in the past or the present who make the distinction between classifications and systems/arrangements, a natural system of classification is an oxymoron: the reason such people speak of natural systems is because nature isn't arranged in classes. A very special conflict arose once people accepted the notion of evolution and it became clear that the true arrangement of living diversity (the natural system) is a tree. This conflict arose because there are two kinds of tree diagrams: (1) "logical trees" representing classificatory relations, and (2) historical, genealogical trees: "trees of history". I can make a "logical tree" showing the classification of furniture into chairs and tables, and then into desk chairs, dining chairs, lounge chairs, etc. Such a "tree" however is purely a classificatory device that has nothing whatever to do with evolutionary, genealogical, "trees of history", in which the root is an actual organism or population that lived in the past. One of the most troublesome problems in the history of systematics has been the confusion of logical trees and trees of history, that is, classifications and phylogenies. It is an empirical fact that people within and without the field of systematics have found "group thinking" to be easy and intuitive, but "tree thinking" (historical/genealogical tree thinking) to be extremely difficult. It is possible to see the seeds of this confusion in the classification chapter (XIII) in the first edition of the _Origin of Species_ where Darwin distinguishes precisely between classification and arrangement in several places (and here he owes much to an earlier paper by Wallace, I believe) but doesn't really develop all the consequences that result from this distinction, especially in view of the fact that many traditional groups were clearly not whole branches of the evolutionary tree (the logical and genealogical trees did not match). Because the full implications of the classification/phylogeny distinction were not genuinely internalized in systematics until quite recently, some people have spoken of the Darwinian revolution in systematics -- the idea that systematics is really about reconstructing evolutionary history, and that the natural system is in fact the sequence of events (the "chronicle") that make up the evolutionary past -- as being effected only within the last 20 years or so. This is a view with which I agree. Now, is classification per se a valuable thing to study from the point of view of the history of systematics? Absolutely it is, in precisely the same way that phlogiston theory is important to study in the history of chemistry, and astrology is important to the history of astronomy. And it is certain that there are elements of "group thinking" still present in systematics today that need to be eliminated; study of classification will help us to understand why these persist and how people regard them. But theoretical considerations of "classification" as a distinct intellectual practice are not relevant to the contemporary _practice_ of systematics, which has as its task the reconstruction of evolutionary history. There is nothing that sounds more utterly barren today than the debates of the 1970s over "my way of classifying is better than your way of classifying." Incidentally, I understood along with Margaret Winters that the famous "Chinese classification" that has been posted here a couple times already, and which comes from Foucault, was actually taken by Foucault from Borges. I also understood that Borges made the whole thing up (which makes attempts to "analyze" it look pretty silly). Whether or not Borges made it up, I have always regarded that example as prima facie evidence that the whole subject of classification is irrelevant to evolutionary biology, because that example has nothing to do with reconstructing history. Anyone who wants to look at a literary example that _is_ relevant to historical reconstruction and representation might try another Borges story, "The Garden of Forking Paths", which is about branching histories and contingency. It is anthologized in his book _Labyrinths_, I believe, and should be available in most libraries. Bob O'Hara, Darwin-L list owner Robert J. O'Hara (darwin@iris.uncg.edu) Center for Critical Inquiry and Department of Biology 100 Foust Building, University of North Carolina at Greensboro Greensboro, North Carolina 27412 U.S.A.
Your Amazon purchases help support this website. Thank you!