rjohara.net |
Darwin-L Message Log 2:156 (October 1993)
Academic Discussion on the History and Theory of the Historical Sciences
This is one message from the Archives of Darwin-L (1993–1997), a professional discussion group on the history and theory of the historical sciences.
Note: Additional publications on evolution and the historical sciences by the Darwin-L list owner are available on SSRN.
<2:156>From DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Sat Oct 30 00:33:32 1993 Date: Sat, 30 Oct 1993 01:39:45 -0400 (EDT) From: DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Subject: Some notes on historical explanation To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Organization: University of NC at Greensboro Tom Cravens asks about explanation in the historical sciences, and Professor Gale prompts me as well, so I guess I had better post a few notes. Since George is actually teaching this material, and I only dabble in it (wishing I could take his course), I hope he'll supplement what I have to say as he sees fit. (Maybe he could just upload a lecture or two.) ;-) As Tom noted, the whole topic of explanation is a huge can of worms, but it is an interesting and delectible one. I think there's lots of room for important and innovative work here, because much of what has been written about explanation in the historical sciences has used models of explanation that were developed originally in the context of the non-historical experimental and physical sciences. One of the things I have tried to do in my own work is explore some of the literature on explanation in history generally, and from what I have seen there are a lot of ideas in that literature that could be fruitfully applied to problems in the historical sciences. While many people in the historical sciences have some familiarity with the philosophy of science, the philosophy of _history_ remains a very small and very much under-studied field for reasons that largely escape me. Anyone who wants to consider philosophical issues in the historical sciences, though, really ought to delve into the philosophy of history, because that's where the most relevant work will be found, in my opinion. What follows is just brief sketch-map of the territory to supplement what George already posted; it may help people orient themselves with respect to the topic and provide a few useful references. One of most important early twentieth-century views of historical explanation and understanding, usually associated with the work of Robin Collingwood (1946), was the "reenactment" view: we understand the actions of Caesar when we can reenact in our own minds the thoughts he had, and see how they led him to take the actions that he took. The development of a sense of sympathetic understanding has always been considered important by historians, and Collingwood's reenactment notion attempts to capture this. But this is in many respects the least interesting view of historical explanation and understanding from the point of view of the historical sciences, because "history" for Collingwood was only the history of human actions: the earth has no "history" for him, because it is not a rational being whose mind we can enter. This is clearly a very narrow definition of "history", and Toulmin & Goodfield responded to it quite effectively in the introduction to their book _The Discovery of Time_ (1965). During the mid-twentieth century most discussion of historical explanation focussed on the so-called covering law model of explanation that George Gale mentioned. This model of explanation is usually associated with Carl Hempel, who tried to extend it from its original home in the physical sciences into history in a very influential paper published in 1942. Much of this work is considered old hat nowadays, but it was important because it drove a number of people who didn't like Hempel's project to examine carefully just what historical explanation and understanding were like, under the assumption they were not just immature versions of physics as Hempel had seemed to imply. Beginning in the 1950s, partly in reaction to Hempel, a number of people began developing autonomous theories of historical explanation and understanding under the general rubric of "analytical philosophy of history". Some of the principal actors involved were (and are) William Dray, Morton White, Arthur Danto, Louis Mink, William Gallie, Patrick Gardner, W. H. Walsh, and Alan Donagan; if you search a good library catalog under these names you will turn up lots of titles. Recent collections of the work of these people that I have found particularly useful include Dray (1989) and Mink (1987). With regard to narrative representation (though not necessarily explanation) I have found, and continue to find, Danto's _Narration and Knowledge_ (1985) very valuable. The analytical philosophers of history tried to characterize a number of kinds of explanations used in historical writing in addition to the covering-law type discussed by Hempel. These included narratives, continuous series explanations, integrating explanations, how-possibly explanations, and others. David Hull, a noted philosopher of evolutionary biology, wrote a very nice paper (1975) on integrating explanations that deserves more attention than it has had; and I've applied Dray's notion of "how-possibly" explanations to evolutionary biology in one of my own papers (1988). Some of the most recent work in these areas has been influenced by literary theories of narrative. People like Hayden White and Paul Ricoeur are important in this context, though I have tended to find this work less accessible to me as a scientist than the earlier work of Danto, Dray, and their allies. This is just the briefest of sketches; there is a good deal of recent literature in these areas that I have not followed closely. The journal _History and Theory_ (the principal journal in philosophy of history) regularly publishes papers on all aspects of historical explanation and understanding, and is a good place to look to find out what's going on. Literature cited above: Collingwood, Robin G. 1946. _The Idea of History_. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Danto, Arthur C. 1985. _Narration and Knowledge_. New York: Columbia University Press. Dray, William. 1989. _On History and Philosophers of History_. Leiden: E. J. Brill. (Excellent volume of selected papers.) Hempel, Carl G. 1942. The function of general laws in history. _Journal of Philosophy_, 39:35-48. (Reprinted in Hempel's selected papers volume, the title of which I don't recall.) Hull, David L. 1975. Central subjects and historical narratives. _History and Theory_, 14:253-274. (Reprinted in Hull's selected papers volume _The Metaphysics of Evolution_, 1989.) Mink, Louis O. 1987. _Historical Understanding_ (B. Fay, E. O. Golub, & R. T. Vann, eds.). Ithaca: Cornell University Press. (Excellent volume of selected papers.) O'Hara, Robert J. 1988. Homage to Clio, or, toward an historical philosophy for evolutionary biology. _Systematic Zoology_, 37:142-155. Toulmin, Stephen E., & June Goodfield. 1965. _The Discovery of Time_. New York: Harper and Row. (Reprinted by University of Chicago Press. The single best book on the historical sciences, in my opinion.) Bob O'Hara, Darwin-L list owner Robert J. O'Hara (darwin@iris.uncg.edu) Center for Critical Inquiry and Department of Biology 100 Foust Building, University of North Carolina at Greensboro Greensboro, North Carolina 27412 U.S.A.
Your Amazon purchases help support this website. Thank you!