rjohara.net |
Darwin-L Message Log 7:66 (March 1994)
Academic Discussion on the History and Theory of the Historical Sciences
This is one message from the Archives of Darwin-L (1993–1997), a professional discussion group on the history and theory of the historical sciences.
Note: Additional publications on evolution and the historical sciences by the Darwin-L list owner are available on SSRN.
<7:66>From DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Fri Mar 18 23:32:37 1994 Date: Sat, 19 Mar 1994 00:32:33 -0500 (EST) From: DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Subject: Hominid evolution and "species" (II) To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Organization: University of NC at Greensboro Ken Jacobs proposed that one of the sources of confusion in the debates about recent hominid evolution was a tendency toward what I call "group thinking." Kent Holsinger took exception to Ken's interpretation, but I want to suggest that both Ken and Kent are really pointing to the same problem, though they are arriving at it from different directions. Kent wrote: The question, is whether _H. erectus_ and _H. sapiens_ are related anagenetically or cladogenetically. For those not familiar with the terms, let me explain. Imagine the following tree of relationships: A B C \ / / \/ / D / \ / \ / E | | Species A and B share a more recent common ancestor with one another (D) than either shares with C (E). Anagenesis is evolutionary change that happens *along* the branches, i.e., from E to C, E to D, D to A, or D to B. Cladogeneis is the process that leads to splitting of lineages, i.e., the process that takes the single lineage leading to E and splits it into two, one leading to A and B, the other to C. Similarly, cladogenesis occurs at D producing two lineages. The multiregional hypothesis suggests that _H. erectus_ and _H. sapiens_ are related anagenetically. The single origin hypothesis suggests that they are related cladogenetically. As I said in my early reply to Bayla Singer (though not in these words), I know of no case other than the origin of human beings where evolutionary biologists have postulated (in the last twenty years at least) an anagenetic relationship between two widely distributed species. Kent's explanation here is exactly correct. The problem as I see it, though, is that at the population level the notions of cladogenesis and anagenesis are somewhat ill-defined. In other words, when we resolve a tree like the one shown above down to a greater level of detail, it is not entirely clear which populational events represent "branching" and which do not. It might be the case that some populations split off for a time (cladogenesis), and then partially merge back in to other populations; there might be a more or less complete cladogenetic event (a split) but there might still be some occasional gene flow between the resulting lineages. What anthropologists refer to as "_Homo erectus_" and "_Homo sapiens_" may be related cladogenetically or anagenetically, but it may also be that the historical interconnections between these two "species" is something of a combination between the anagenesis and cladogenesis, especially at certain time depths. The new issue of _Systematic Biology_ that just arrived this week has a very nice case study that illustrates these problems; folks interested in the issue of species delimitation in the hominid case might find it very interesting and helpful: Patton, J. L., & M. F. Smith. 1994. Paraphyly, polyphyly, and the nature of species boundaries in pocket gophers (genus _Thomomys_). _Systematic Biology_, 43(3):11-26. From the abstract: "These molecular perspectives [described in the paper] give somewhat conflicting views of polyphyly, paraphyly, and monophyly at the population and species level due, in part, to probable differences in times to monophyly, differential lineage sorting, retention of ancestral polymorphisms, and/or episodes of asymmetrical introgressive hybridization. As a consequence, strict adherence to any species concept in the objective recognition of evolutionary units within this complex is difficult at best." (Sounds like _Homo_, yes?) I have also written a theoretical piece that addresses many of the same questions, and it might be of interest to the anthropologists who are concerned with the conceptual roots of these problems as well: O'Hara, R. J. 1993. Systematic generalization, historical fate, and the species problem. _Systematic Biology_, 42(3):231-246. This paper contains some nice diagrams (I like to think ;-) that might be useful for people trying to picture the complexity of the tree when viewed up close in the vicinity of a branch point. Not wanting to leave our other historical scientists out of this discussion, I hope that any brave linguists who have been following this thread can see that what is being talked about here is the problem of when does one language become two languages, how do we decide whether to populations of speakers are speaking two different languages or two dialects of the same language, are the similarities between two languages the result of borrowing (introgression) or independent origin, etc. Systematists have traditionally worried a lot more about these questions, I think, with respect to species than linguists ever have with respect to languages. That is probably because the original assumption of our field was that "species" were by definition independent creations, and did not share ancestors in common. The existence of "doubtful species" (as Darwin called them) was and is one of the main pieces of evidence against independent creation and for the fact of evolutionary history. Bob O'Hara, Darwin-L list owner Robert J. O'Hara (darwin@iris.uncg.edu) Center for Critical Inquiry and Department of Biology 100 Foust Building, University of North Carolina at Greensboro Greensboro, North Carolina 27412 U.S.A.
Your Amazon purchases help support this website. Thank you!