rjohara.net |
Darwin-L Message Log 1: 171–200 — September 1993
Academic Discussion on the History and Theory of the Historical Sciences
Darwin-L was an international discussion group on the history and theory of the historical sciences, active from 1993–1997. Darwin-L was established to promote the reintegration of a range of fields all of which are concerned with reconstructing the past from evidence in the present, and to encourage communication among scholars, scientists, and researchers in these fields. The group had more than 600 members from 35 countries, and produced a consistently high level of discussion over its several years of operation. Darwin-L was not restricted to evolutionary biology nor to the work of Charles Darwin, but instead addressed the entire range of historical sciences from an explicitly comparative perspective, including evolutionary biology, historical linguistics, textual transmission and stemmatics, historical geology, systematics and phylogeny, archeology, paleontology, cosmology, historical geography, historical anthropology, and related “palaetiological” fields.
This log contains public messages posted to the Darwin-L discussion group during September 1993. It has been lightly edited for format: message numbers have been added for ease of reference, message headers have been trimmed, some irregular lines have been reformatted, and error messages and personal messages accidentally posted to the group as a whole have been deleted. No genuine editorial changes have been made to the content of any of the posts. This log is provided for personal reference and research purposes only, and none of the material contained herein should be published or quoted without the permission of the original poster.
The master copy of this log is maintained in the Darwin-L Archives (rjohara.net/darwin) by Dr. Robert J. O’Hara. The Darwin-L Archives also contain additional information about the Darwin-L discussion group, the complete Today in the Historical Sciences calendar for every month of the year, a collection of recommended readings on the historical sciences, and an account of William Whewell’s concept of “palaetiology.”
------------------------------------------------- DARWIN-L MESSAGE LOG 1: 171-200 -- SEPTEMBER 1993 ------------------------------------------------- DARWIN-L A Network Discussion Group on the History and Theory of the Historical Sciences Darwin-L@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu is an international network discussion group on the history and theory of the historical sciences. Darwin-L was established in September 1993 to promote the reintegration of a range of fields all of which are concerned with reconstructing the past from evidence in the present, and to encourage communication among academic professionals in these fields. Darwin-L is not restricted to evolutionary biology nor to the work of Charles Darwin but instead addresses the entire range of historical sciences from an interdisciplinary perspective, including evolutionary biology, historical linguistics, textual transmission and stemmatics, historical geology, systematics and phylogeny, archeology, paleontology, cosmology, historical anthropology, historical geography, and related "palaetiological" fields. This log contains public messages posted to Darwin-L during September 1993. It has been lightly edited for format: message numbers have been added for ease of reference, message headers have been trimmed, some irregular lines have been reformatted, and error messages and personal messages accidentally posted to the group as a whole have been deleted. No genuine editorial changes have been made to the content of any of the posts. This log is provided for personal reference and research purposes only, and none of the material contained herein should be published or quoted without the permission of the original poster. The master copy of this log is maintained in the archives of Darwin-L by listserv@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu. For instructions on how to retrieve copies of this and other log files, and for additional information about Darwin-L, send the e-mail message INFO DARWIN-L to listserv@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu. Darwin-L is administered by Robert J. O'Hara (darwin@iris.uncg.edu), Center for Critical Inquiry in the Liberal Arts and Department of Biology, University of North Carolina at Greensboro, Greensboro, North Carolina 27412 U.S.A., and it is supported by the Center for Critical Inquiry, University of North Carolina at Greensboro, and the Department of History and the Academic Computing Center, University of Kansas. _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:171>From LUKEMATT@macc.wisc.edu Sat Sep 18 09:09:49 1993 Date: Sat, 18 Sep 93 09:10 CDT From: J. Luke Matthews <LUKEMATT@macc.wisc.edu> Subject: Re: Evolution and its mechanisms To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu can organisms evolve into simpler organisms? Aren't some parasites examples of such simplifying processes? Luke Matthews LUKEMATT@MACC.WISC.EDU _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:172>From loring@maroon.tc.umn.edu Sat Sep 18 13:05:47 1993 Date: Sat, 18 Sep 1993 12:54:33 -0500 (CDT) From: "Anne M Loring-1" <loring@maroon.tc.umn.edu> Subject: Women, Fire and Dangerous Things To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu On Sat, 18 Sep 1993, Mary P Winsor wrote: > You suggest that those interested in the supposed Chinese taxonomy > found in Borges should read Lakoff "WOmen, fire and dangerous things" > from which I assume you have read it. I'm sure others in the list > besides me would be helped if you would tell us in a sentence or three > what Lakoff is about. Will do. Lakoff is a linguist at UC Berkeley. His book _Women, Fire and Dangerous Things_ (U of Chicago Press, 1987) is subtitled "What categories reveal about the mind". Those of you interested in taxonomy might wonder what any of this has to do with classifying ferns, lizards, minerals, or the like. Lakoff is interesting because he challenges us to look at our (pre?)conceptions about categorization. He quotes the passage from Borges with the commentary that "people around the world categorize things in ways that both boggle the Western mind and stump Western linguists and anthropologists", going on to cite an actual classical system used by speakers of Dyirbal (an Australian aboriginal language) that rivals the list of categories in Borges for mind-bogglingness. (see pages 92-93 for a quick read) Get back to me if any of you want to discuss Lakoff further. Anne Loring <loring@maroon.tc.umn.edu> _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:173>From DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Sat Sep 18 16:50:25 1993 Date: Sat, 18 Sep 1993 17:21:06 -0400 (EDT) From: DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Subject: Phylogeny (history) is important, classification is not To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Organization: University of NC at Greensboro We have had much discussion of classification. Along with many other people in evolutionary biology today, I don't find the topic of classification to be a fruitful one, and I would like to make the strong claim that classification is almost completely irrelevant to the contemporary practice of evolutionary biology. This is because much discussion of "classification" in fact fails to make a very important distinction now made within evolutionary biology between two different activities: (1) classifying (making groups), and (2) reconstructing phylogeny (evolutionary history). Until this distinction is clearly made there really can't be any fruitful discussion of either classification or phylogeny. This whole subject has been _enormously_ clarified in the last 15 years or so, and all practicioners in the field now make this distinction clearly. Here's a sketch of my reading of the situation; I'm sure my views are not universally held in all their details, but neither are they unique. Every paragraph below could easily be given monographic treatment, and many have been; my aim here is just to give a broad sketch for those who have an interest in the subject but have not followed the literature closely. We have among our members some leading historians of systematics and some leading systematists, so I apologize if I do violence to any of their views in the interest of brevity. While my comments address evolutionary biology, I like to think they have implications for historical linguistics and stemmatics as well. The last 25 years has seen an enormous growth in the study of phylogeny, the evolutionary history of life. This was one of the great fields of study in the late 1800s, but for much of the early and mid-20th century phylogeny was comparatively negleced in favor of studies of evolutionary mechanisms and "species-level" problems. (This species-level work was enormously important of course, and it is still with us.) Since the mid 1960s, however, interest in phylogeny has grown enormously due to three factors: (1) the development of computational methods for dealing with large quantities of data; (2) the availability of data on comparative molecular anatomy, though this has not been as important to the conceptual development of the phylogenetics revolution as the popular press (and some molecular biologists) would have people believe; and most importantly (3) a new conceptual understanding of the relationship between the observed similarities and differences among organisms and the histories that can be inferred from those similarities and differences. This last factor is behind the method of "cladistic analysis" which has effected a revolution in the study of phylogeny, and which is now the standard method for reconstructing evolutionary history. The conceptual development of cladistic analysis in the last 30 years or so has been as important to systematics as the development of the law of superposition -- that upper strata are younger than lower ones -- was long ago to geology. The briefest sketch of the long view of this subject would go like this (many of these statements could be qualified; there is an increasing body of published literature on this). Beginning in the 1600s and 1700s there was an enormous increase in factual knowledge of natural diversity on the part of European scientists. The notion of a linear "chain of being" which had been the principal organizing system for diversity up until that time came, as a consequence, to be challenged in the late 1700s and early 1800s, and a variety of other arrangements were conceived for the diversity of life, including maps, stars, circles, nets, and trees. Notice that I spoke here of _arrangements_. It is entirely true that may students of diversity engaged in classification and published classifications. But many theorists even during this early period argued that "classification" was not the right intellectual model for understanding and representing the structure of living diversity. In simplest terms, classifications are based on group-within-group relations; _arrangements_ may be based on group-within-group relations but also on some sort of positional relations in an abstract space: taxa are not only contained within other taxa, they are also near and far, between, above or below other taxa. Think of the difference between a printed listing of states, counties, and cities (group-within-group), and contrast that with a map of those same places showing their positions in geographical space. The chain of being is an example of a linear _arrangement_; it is not strictly speaking a classification because it contains a linear axis along which taxa must be placed. The term "system" was often used as a synonym of "arrangement", and people came to speak of "the natural system" -- that is, the true arrangement of the diversity of life. From this notion of system we derive the term "systematics" which is used for the field today. Many important workers in the early 1800s directly contrasted classifications (which they regard as inferior) with systems/arrangements, among them Macleay and Alfred Russel Wallace. One sometimes hears people say "a natural system of classification", but to the workers in the past or the present who make the distinction between classifications and systems/arrangements, a natural system of classification is an oxymoron: the reason such people speak of natural systems is because nature isn't arranged in classes. A very special conflict arose once people accepted the notion of evolution and it became clear that the true arrangement of living diversity (the natural system) is a tree. This conflict arose because there are two kinds of tree diagrams: (1) "logical trees" representing classificatory relations, and (2) historical, genealogical trees: "trees of history". I can make a "logical tree" showing the classification of furniture into chairs and tables, and then into desk chairs, dining chairs, lounge chairs, etc. Such a "tree" however is purely a classificatory device that has nothing whatever to do with evolutionary, genealogical, "trees of history", in which the root is an actual organism or population that lived in the past. One of the most troublesome problems in the history of systematics has been the confusion of logical trees and trees of history, that is, classifications and phylogenies. It is an empirical fact that people within and without the field of systematics have found "group thinking" to be easy and intuitive, but "tree thinking" (historical/genealogical tree thinking) to be extremely difficult. It is possible to see the seeds of this confusion in the classification chapter (XIII) in the first edition of the _Origin of Species_ where Darwin distinguishes precisely between classification and arrangement in several places (and here he owes much to an earlier paper by Wallace, I believe) but doesn't really develop all the consequences that result from this distinction, especially in view of the fact that many traditional groups were clearly not whole branches of the evolutionary tree (the logical and genealogical trees did not match). Because the full implications of the classification/phylogeny distinction were not genuinely internalized in systematics until quite recently, some people have spoken of the Darwinian revolution in systematics -- the idea that systematics is really about reconstructing evolutionary history, and that the natural system is in fact the sequence of events (the "chronicle") that make up the evolutionary past -- as being effected only within the last 20 years or so. This is a view with which I agree. Now, is classification per se a valuable thing to study from the point of view of the history of systematics? Absolutely it is, in precisely the same way that phlogiston theory is important to study in the history of chemistry, and astrology is important to the history of astronomy. And it is certain that there are elements of "group thinking" still present in systematics today that need to be eliminated; study of classification will help us to understand why these persist and how people regard them. But theoretical considerations of "classification" as a distinct intellectual practice are not relevant to the contemporary _practice_ of systematics, which has as its task the reconstruction of evolutionary history. There is nothing that sounds more utterly barren today than the debates of the 1970s over "my way of classifying is better than your way of classifying." Incidentally, I understood along with Margaret Winters that the famous "Chinese classification" that has been posted here a couple times already, and which comes from Foucault, was actually taken by Foucault from Borges. I also understood that Borges made the whole thing up (which makes attempts to "analyze" it look pretty silly). Whether or not Borges made it up, I have always regarded that example as prima facie evidence that the whole subject of classification is irrelevant to evolutionary biology, because that example has nothing to do with reconstructing history. Anyone who wants to look at a literary example that _is_ relevant to historical reconstruction and representation might try another Borges story, "The Garden of Forking Paths", which is about branching histories and contingency. It is anthologized in his book _Labyrinths_, I believe, and should be available in most libraries. Bob O'Hara, Darwin-L list owner Robert J. O'Hara (darwin@iris.uncg.edu) Center for Critical Inquiry and Department of Biology 100 Foust Building, University of North Carolina at Greensboro Greensboro, North Carolina 27412 U.S.A. _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:174>From mhallbey@magellan.geo.usherb.ca Sun Sep 19 18:34:47 1993 Date: Sun, 19 Sep 1993 19:32:50 -0400 From: mhallbey@magellan.geo.usherb.ca (Mryka Hall-Beyer) To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Subject: Classification in mineralogy The classification discussion has lured me out of lurking! I was trained as a mineralogist, but have wandered far afield into remote sensing. My interest in the historical sciences, apart from multi-temporal satellite images, is personal. I will throw in a few comments on classification in mineralogy. Its relevance is the lack of involvment with any idea of teleology, nor contamination with baggage about "higher" and "lower" forms. Yet many of the issues are similar to those raised. Minerals are grouped together in two ways. The true classification system is a tree, and is based on the chemistry of the mineral. There are sulfides, sulfates, oxides and silicates. The silicates are subdivided according to the SI:O ratio. Further subdivisions occur on the grounds of structure, and the finest distinctions are then made by chemical for- mulae, with "subspecies" being solution series between interchangeable atoms (example: % Fe vs Mg in a certain crystal site). An unknown or possibly new mineral would be placed in this system strictly on the basis of observation: what is its chemical formula and what is its structure? Since these two factors determine macroscopic properties, we often tentatively classify minerals on the basis of appearance in the field. But we are often wrong, as impurities in the mineral can change, for example, the colour. We have our splitters and lumpers, depending on whether one considers impurities to be just that or to indicate a separate mineral species. The second classification is by association of the mineral, and is used to inquire about the mineral's history, and ultimately about the history of larger geological units. This seems similar to environmental variation. In mineralogy I have not heard any discussion that a metamorphic garnet should be classified differently from an igneous garnet. Many chemical differences are typical of a certain environment, some are even diagnostic, but the environment does not enter into the classification of the mineral. Likewise, associations of minerals can go a long way to telling us the environment at the time of mineral formation - temperature, pressure, liquid and gas phases, etc. I wonder if this is in any way related to the geographic variation debate? These are pretty random thoughts, hoping to stimulate some ideas among those who know about biological classifica- tion than I do. In sum, 1.history or geography do not influence the classification system in mineralogy. The system is built entirely on features observable in the isolated mineral. The study of history and geography is informed by mineral classification, but not vice versa. 2. The classification system is nested, tree-like, but it is not necessary to see the tree as in any way heirarchical, but only as the grouping together of increasing numbers of similarities. 3. Simplicity and complexity are in no way interpreted as "better" or "more developed" or even "commoner". -Mryka mhallbey@magellan.geo.usherb.ca _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:175>From barryr@ucmp1.Berkeley.EDU Sun Sep 19 21:39:48 1993 Date: Sun, 19 Sep 93 19:42:42 PDT From: barryr@ucmp1.Berkeley.EDU (Barry Roth) To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Subject: Re: Classification in mineralogy Thing about minerals, a species of silicate can come into being where and whenever you have the right combination of atoms and environment. But each species of plant or animal has a unique history ... br _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:176>From John_Wilkins@udev.monash.edu.au Sun Sep 19 22:30:14 1993 Date: Fri, 17 Sep 1993 11:07:40 +0000 From: John Wilkins <John_Wilkins@udev.monash.edu.au> Subject: Culture, evolution and Lamarck To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Culture, evolution and Lamarck (LONG) On 14 Sept, Morris Simon <msimon7@ua1ix.ua.edu> replied to something I wrote: JW: > Two issues concern me: > > 1. How much is cultural evolution REALLY affected by the so-called > intentionality of social agents? Does this really introduce a lamarckian > element (I think not) MS: The phrasing of your question suggests to me that you regard "cultural evolution" as a "given" process. The monolithic view of social darwinism is now a remote 'racial' memory, having been replaced by its very distant decendants, "universal" and "multilinear" evolutionism. Both are oriented toward the use of energy in food production, and both are mainly applicable to cultural systems which no longer exist. In my view, there are certainly no "Lamarckian" influences underlying more recent theories of cultural evolution. JW: > 2. What are the close analogies and the disanalogies between cultural and > biological evolution (Gould, eg, thinks that the term "evolution" ought to be > restricted to biology -- I think because he thinks cultural change is a > directed and staged process). MS: I share the thought you attribute to Gould. I seldom find theories of cultural evolution to be very useful, either to explain well-documented cases of culture change or to analyze ongoing change processes as they occur in modern cultures. The "multilinear" model of Julian Steward, with its central concept of "cultural ecology," is more interesting to me than the energy-based constructs of the "universalists" after Leslie White, but neither of these modern cultural evolution theories share essential analogies with biolgical evolution to a degree which justifies labelling them as "evolutionary." =============== While Anax wrote: While the mechanism of Lamarck was the inheritance of aquired characteristics (and I admit my example on dog breeding was a poor choice), the overall point that Lamarck tried to make was that 'lower' forms of life arose from inanimate matter and progressed towards a level of greater complexity and perfection; that is, that all things had an inherent drive towards greater complexity. For lamarck, the environment operated as the guiding force, directing the increase in complexity towards some end that would create the 'perfect' organism. While this sounds logical, its a bit different from natural selection in which the environment just removes those forms which don't work, allowing a number of possible solutions to and environmental 'problem'. Thinking over your message and previos ones, I find it hard to see how society and culture could be modelled in terms of evolution and natural selection. While society does change, and it would be interesting to be able to predict the changes, I don't think evolution would be quite the right word for it. Half the discussion on this list seems to deal in one sense or another with clarifying the definition of the term evolution, as quite a number of people have been using it in a sloppy sense. Maybe Gould was right - evolution should be restricted to the life sciences and another term sought for the mechanisms that guide human culture. ================== I would like to take this up in a bit of detail. Yes, I do take cultural evolution to be a given. That is -- I consider the changes that occur in certain circumstances to be purely darwinian evolutionary processes ["darwinian" means here generalised processes of the sort that in biology are Darwinian evolutionary processes; typically, hereditary variation that is random with respect to economic selection pressures]. The usual disanalogies presented to cultural evolution are that it is intentional (and therefore neo-lamarckian), that not all change is evolutionary, that history is progressive or staged, and that much of culture is inadaptive (the persistence of obviously wrong cosmologies, etc). In response to this, I would answer that all the above objections have been made to biological Darwinism (the neo-Lamarckists, pre-Synthetic geneticists, romantic philosophers such as Shaw or Koestler, and the recent debates on optimality, in order), and that no evidence has come to my attention to establish without question that evolutionary theories in a sense that Gould would be happy with cannot be generalised and applied to culture. There are going to be strong and weak selective processes. A number of cultural institutions will survive and even change simply because they have no adaptive significance. The interesting cases will be those institutions that, like science, have variations that are strongly selected in terms of differential resource acquisition as well as having strong transmission of traits. The gene-equivalents I call 'transmits' following Toulmin, rather than 'memes' following Dawkins, since I do not wish to commit myself to a units-of-selection debate in culture. Culture is going to be at least as complex if not several orders of magnitude greater than biology, since it is at least supervenient upon biological processes. In my view, it is an emergent level on biology, and has several levels within its domain. Why cannot such strong processes be modelled darwinianly? Economics has obvious evolutionary/ecological parallels, and is viewed anything but lamarkian by an increasing number of economists (the "rational-man" theory seems to have had its day, although even here I would argue that the parallel is with game-theoretic analyses of genetic interest -- more a useful calculative fiction than an echt account of how entities "choose" to gamble). The real difficulty in modelling cultural evolution is to (a) determine what counts as a 'transmit' (Dawkins instances a snatch of a tune or a form of lyrics; Hull, a theory or professional citation; Cavalli-Sforza and Feldman use economic examples and linguistic transformations, and so forth), and (b) to establish what the selective advantages are -- ie, what the economic resources the acquisition of which affect differential transmission are. I do not see why we need to posit simple unary explanations for the entire range of cultural process -- an example from science need not work in linguistics. If we can model a restricted domain darwinianly, and rid ourselves of the myth of rational change (where it is a myth), that is in itself useful. Incidentally, there are three senses of Lamarckism -- the inheritance of acquired characteristics (the usual sense applicable to cultural evolutionary theories, which Darwin shared and was not invented by Lamarck); progressivist perfectionism and/or a scale of being from lower to higher forms; and the view that striving affects the evolutionary process in the direction striven. All three senses are applied in criticism of cultural evolution models. It is clear to me, at any rate, that history is *not* a series of predetermined developmental stages, nor is it in the long term progressive. Societies and cultures, schools and institutions, all wax and wane according to how well they do compared with their competitors. They are populational entities, with transmitted structures. There are transformation rules between the developmental and economic spaces (to adapt a model of Lewontin's) in culture as in biology. So, why not? John Wilkins, Monash University, Australia _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:177>From John_Wilkins@udev.monash.edu.au Sun Sep 19 22:38:24 1993 Date: Mon, 13 Sep 1993 11:04:32 +0000 From: John Wilkins <John_Wilkins@udev.monash.edu.au> Subject: Cultural evolution To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Reply to: Cultural evolution J. Luke Matthews <LUKEMATT@macc.wisc.edu>noted: it's interesting how the name Lamarck comes up anytime the word 'intentionality' comes up when people talk about evolution. Changes in culture, society aren't different from changes in the non-human parts of the universe...their's plenty of intentionality out there too...after all (and this is admittedly an exaggeration) one reason there are no jellyfish on mountaintops is because jellyfish just hate montane environments. Animals and plants, monera, protista, and whatever else are squirming around out there do have some capacity to make some (perhaps severely limited) choices. And of course, there's plenty of irrational and nonrational nonintentionality among us ever so sapient humans. I reply: Indeed. The existence of a "rational" choice (that is, an actual decision, as opposed to game-theoretic descriptions of selection like Maynard Smith's and Dawkins') merely adds more variation to fuel selection. Unless it is assumed that "striving" somehow determines the success of the variation (the neo-Lamarckian assumption), then the fact that a cultural variant arose from a conscious decision to solve a problem is of no relevance to an evolutionary model of cultural change, *even of science*, any more than artificial selection somehow works differently to natural selection for the same reason (artificial selection is a subset of natural selection). John Wilkins - Manager, Publishing Monash University, Melbourne Australia Internet: john_wilkins@udev.monash.edu.au Tel: (+613) 565 6009 Monash and I often, but not always, concur _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:178>From LANGDON@GANDLF.UINDY.EDU Mon Sep 20 10:47:21 1993 Date: Mon, 20 Sep 1993 10:47:21 -0500 From: "JOHN LANGDON" <LANGDON@GANDLF.UINDY.EDU> To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Subject: Re: Lamarkianism in linguistic change In message <930918095527.26402829@FENNEL.WT.UWA.EDU.AU> writes: > "Kent E. Holsinger" <HOLSINGE%UCONNVM.BITNET@KUHUB.CC.UKANS.EDU> > noted in a very good anaylsis of the danger of purely allelic defintions of > evolution that > > Including some notion of genetic or hereditary change is important. > ~~~~~~~~~~~~~~ > > Evolution hasn't happened unless there is some difference between the > > characteristics of ancestors and descendants. > > As a biologist/archaeologist who works with evolution in a purely > phenotypic system (human culture), I think the "or" in his statement is > exceedingly important. Non-genetic hereditary stytems are quite as > amenable to Darwinian analysis as genetic ones (which is no surprise given > that the model was developed well before we knew anything about genetic > systems!). To me, heritable implies genetic or some other biologically determined change. Culture is not heritable and the evolution of culture is not better than an analogy with organic evolution. What non-genetic systems do you have in mind? The important factor in ALL systems capable of evolution, of > course, is selection in terms of fitness (something that seems to have been > a tad overlooked in the "definitions" of evolution posted thus far). Seen > in these terms, evolution is the result of the selection of hereditable > traits over time (hence, changes in allelic frequencies, etc., are merely > CONSEQUENCES of selection and therefore provide a fairly poor basis for a > definition of it). Changes in allelic frequences are part of the definition of evolution, not selection. Evolution may reflect selection, but may also reflect non-selected changes. The two should not be interchanged. Incidently, I disagree that evolution cannot be applied to systems that change without selection for fitness-- e.g. geological change is evolution even though there is nothing giving direction to it. JOHN H. LANGDON email langdon@gandlf.uindy.edu DEPARTMENT OF BIOLOGY phone (317) 788-3447 UNIVERSITY OF INDIANAPOLIS FAX (317) 788-3569 1400 EAST HANNA AVENUE INDIANAPOLIS, IN 46227 _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:179>From HOLSINGE@UCONNVM.BITNET Mon Sep 20 12:19:25 1993 Date: Mon, 20 Sep 1993 08:36:33 -0500 (EST) From: "Kent E. Holsinger" <HOLSINGE%UCONNVM.BITNET@KUHUB.CC.UKANS.EDU> Subject: Re: Culture, evolution and Lamarck To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu It strikes me in reading the discussion about the possibility of cultural evolution that an important distinction is being missed, viz. the distinction between Darwin's theory of evolution and his theory of evolution by natural selection. Darwin's theory of evolution consists of the assertion that all of life's diversity can be explained as a result of descent with modification from a a single common ancestor. Descent with modification is the _only_ process specified. It includes both the branching of lineages and transformation within lineages. It doesn't specify anything about the mechanism that produces the branching or the transformation. In fact, as Ernst Mayr is fond of pointing out, Darwin mostly ignored the problem of how branching happens, focusing instead on the mechanics of transformation within lineages. Darwin's theory of natural selection is one mechanism by which evolutionary change can happen. It is the idea that types with a superior "fitness" will be more greatly represented in succeeding generations than those with a lesser fitness. It is _not_ the only mechanism of evolutionary change, nor is it the only mechanism that Darwin proposed. Darwin envisioned both the inheritance of acquired characteristics and use & disuse of parts as important sources of evolutionary change. We now know that additional processes, like genetic drift, can lead to evolutionary change in a population in the absence of natural selection. Taking this distinction as a given, I can see no reason why we can't talk about (at least certain forms of) cultural evolution. It may be difficult to define the characteristics that are changing, but ask any biological taxonomist how they define a "character" of an organism and you'll see that the problem is not unique to culture. Given that we can identify some characteristics of a culture, say language practices, and given that those characteristics change over time it seems likely to me that the changes can be understood in the broad framework of descent with modification. In fact, my limited understanding of linguistics suggests that this is precisely the case, the similarity of Romance languages being due to their common heritage in classical Latin and the resemblance of Germanic, Romance, and other languages being due to their common heritage in Indo-European. There are, of course, interesting ways in which cultural evolution differs from biological evolution, e.g., greater reticulation among lineages (especially now) and the potential for inheritance of acquired characters (what _is_ education, after all?). These differences, however, have to do with the _mechanisms_ responsible for producing descent with modification. Thus, I see cultural evolution as a historical process that will share some of the features of biological evolution, simply because both are a process of descent with modification, even though the mechanisms underlying biological and cultural evolution are very different. -- Kent _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:180>From GA3704@SIUCVMB.SIU.EDU Mon Sep 20 12:36:05 1993 Date: Mon, 20 Sep 93 12:04:05 CST From: "Margaret E. Winters" <GA3704@SIUCVMB.SIU.EDU> To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Subject: Lakoff What Lakoff is doing in "Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things" - to expand a little on what was said - is to propose that categorization is not just used for things, but for mental objects as well (not a new idea) including linguistic items (his contribution). We categorize grammatical constructions as well as words, all of this in terms of `best instances' or prototypes (see the work of the psychologist Eleanor Rosch) and better or worse instances which are arranged around these prototypical examples. Warning - the book is not easy to read since it is not as well organized as one would wish (I've read it a couple of times and worked through it with students). I particularly recommend, however, that you look at the case studies at the back which are somewhat easier to follow and really give a sense of what is so exciting about what Lakoff is doing. Margaret Winters <ga3704@siucvmb.siu.edu> _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:181>From SOSLEWIS@ACS.EKU.EDU Mon Sep 20 14:48:32 1993 Date: Mon, 20 Sep 1993 15:50:26 -0400 (EDT) From: SOSLEWIS@ACS.EKU.EDU Subject: Re: Culture, evolution and Lama To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu I am not certain how important any of you would view this comment regarding cultural evolution, but I find it somewhat to separate the biological completely from cultural evolution if for no other reason than the fact Homo sapiens are biological organisms. As the culture changes it must place some "stress" (for want of a better work) on the organisms. Anyway, it may be something to talk about. Ray, EKU soslewis@acs.eku.edu _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:182>From huh@u.washington.edu Mon Sep 20 16:28:12 1993 Date: Mon, 20 Sep 1993 14:20:29 -0700 (PDT) From: Mark Rushing <huh@u.washington.edu> Subject: Re: Lakoff To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu On Mon, 20 Sep 1993, Margaret E. Winters wrote: > What Lakoff is doing in "Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things" - to > expand a little on what was said - is to propose that categorization > is not just used for things, but for mental objects as well (not a > new idea) including linguistic items (his contribution). We categorize > grammatical constructions as well as words, all of this in terms > of `best instances' or prototypes (see the work of the psychologist > Eleanor Rosch) and better or worse instances which are arranged > around these prototypical examples. margaret, i'm curious -- perhaps you are aware of some Fact-based study, or perhaps you might speculate -- how are these categorical groupings interconnected? i suppose you could use, as analogy, a 'primitive' human who plays with a club and cracks open a shell, then some cross-referential process occurs where this same technique is applied to another human skull, then more cross-referential processes occur, etc... from a perspective which may be closer to Home, the 'creative' process in which notions (or Observations) of biological evolutionary process is made a metaphor for societal Institutions. i'm not saying that i believe there is anything wrong with this, but it seems that this sort of creative process is what might 'propel' scientific thought. after all, a dream must occur (a hypothesis) before it can be put on Trial... mark mark rushing post office box 85267 seattle, washington 98145-1267 206.329.8070 huh@u.washington.edu rushing@battelle.org Mark.Rushing@f157.n343.z1.fidonet.org _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:183>From BROWNH@CCSUA.CTSTATEU.EDU Mon Sep 20 18:53:23 1993 Date: Mon, 20 Sep 1993 19:54:47 -0400 (EDT) From: BROWNH@CCSUA.CTSTATEU.EDU To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Subject: RE: Classification in mineralogy Mryka, As an amateur mineralogist, I can't resist reflecting upon your comments. I note that you stress observable characteristics. Since what is observed is a function of the instruments of observation (if humans were color-blind, the color of the mineral would not be taken into consideration), and what is considered to be significant is a function of subjective bias (generally, a small crystal is not classi- fied as a different mineral than a large crystal of the same substance). So, if I may, your "observable qualities" might be elaborated. First, there is a tendency to classify persistent qualities as essential and short range qualities as accidents. The former serves to distin- guish classes (mineral species) from individuals (two specimens of the same species). Also, there are entities that have non-observable quali- ties, such as magnetic fields. So perhaps we can say that there are qualities that distinguish things, either as classes or individuals, and these distinguishing things are what we call empirical qualities. But now the fun begins. If we start out with the assumption that what persists is essential and what changes is accidental, ephemeral, insignificant, then we bring in a profound bias in favor of stability and uniformity. Obviously, persistence is a matter of scale. At the small scale of daily life, we must assume persistence of empirical quali- ties so that we can function in a predictable environment and communicate with others. But in world history, diversity and change is far more evident than continuity and uniformity. Arguably, units such as "civili- zation" is inappropriate in the study of world history because it makes change and diveristy problematic for a reality that has them in its na- ture. The obvious unity in world history would be a "process," not an empirically-defined unit such as culture, society, or civilization. To conceive things as processes can be done, but that takes me away from the subject. I bring this up because various classifications may not be right or wrong, but suited to our purposes to various degrees. If the unit of world history should be represented as a process rather than defined soleyl in empirical terms, that is because we start with the knowledge that world history is in fact complex and changing. With minerals, that] is quite a different situation. Traditionally, our aim has not been to explain why some beryl is green and some yellow, but to impose order on a complexity; frankly, to arrange things on museum shelves (pace, curators, I know this view is justly frowned on today); in long range processes in which change and complexity is of their essence, what becomes signifi- cant for us changes. We seek to explain why things occurred as they did, and for the historian, explanation is always tied time, place and cir- cumstance (as Lenin used to say). For the mineralogiest, general classi- fication suffices. Haines Brown (brownh@ccsua.ctstateu.edu) _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:184>From DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Mon Sep 20 22:34:45 1993 Date: Mon, 20 Sep 1993 20:18:59 -0400 (EDT) From: DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Subject: September 20 -- Today in the Historical Sciences To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Organization: University of NC at Greensboro SEPTEMBER 20 -- TODAY IN THE HISTORICAL SCIENCES 1811: PYOTR SIMON PALLAS dies at Berlin, Germany. A natural historian and geographer of great breadth, Pallas had spent most of his life in Russia, and had investigated topics as diverse as the systematics of corals (_Elenchus Zoophytorum_, 1766), the formation of mountain ranges (1777), animal variation (1780), and phytogeography (_Flora Rossia_, 1784-1788). 1863: JACOB LUDWIG KARL GRIMM dies. With his brother Wilhelm Carl, Jacob Grimm will be remembered as one of the founding fathers of comparative Indo-European philology. Together they edited collections of fairy tales (1812-1815), and Jacob produced one of the earliest comprehensive works on comparative grammar (_Deutsche Grammatik_, 1819-1837). In 1822 Jacob will characterize what is today known as Grimm's law, the regular pattern of consonantal replacement (the replacement of 'p' by 'f', for example) that occurred during the history of the Indo-European languages. Today in the Historical Sciences is a feature of Darwin-L@ukanaix.cc. ukans.edu, a network discussion group on the history and theory of the historical sciences. E-mail darwin@iris.uncg.edu for more information. _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:185>From msimon7@ua1ix.ua.edu Tue Sep 21 09:09:39 1993 Date: Tue, 21 Sep 1993 09:11:12 -0600 (CDT) From: Morris Simon <msimon7@ua1ix.ua.edu> Subject: Re: A reply to Ramsden To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu On Thu, 16 Sep 1993, Mark Rushing wrote: > the problem with Epistomology is that it is easy to become lost in a > categorical tangles. ....... [OMITTED MATERIAL] You bet it's easy, Mark, as you can see from our current exchange. I think we're talking about different things, or about the same thing from very different perspectives. You speak of a "Power structure" [which] "is the Tool we call Science." In fact, I simply spoke of pragmatics of empirical science -- a "power structure" in C.P. Snow circles, perhaps, but not in the ones most of my scientist colleagues and I move in. > well, i'm a poet, not a scientist. i would say that the meaning you find, > if any, is more relevant that anything i could tell you. i simply supply > the words, like a woodcutter shaping small, lettered cubes. maybe they're > made for children. maybe they're like casting runes. maybe they make you > feel angry because this should be Science. No anger here. Just curiosity. > when you say, "a person uses his/her cortex to modify sub-cortical > perceptions" do you notice that Person is outside of his own mind? My clumsy way (science, not poetry) of distinguishing conscious thought from unconscious physiological perception. > so when you look into the world, when you look into the mind of another > person, through their messages (in their eyes, on your screen, in the > vibrational waves through aether), i Believe it is important to attempt to > understand what you are hearing and seeing (perceiving) before you so > abruptly return to the Inner Sanctum to grab the clubs and instruments of > Dialectic Warfare. No flames were intended, I assure you. > large out there. it just bothered me that you were a rifle-toting > Dialectician in an interdisciplinary setting. we have the opportunity to > be so much more.... Ouch! That burned! Was that a bullet, or a red-hot synthesis? > end of appeal to the modern church. Amen. > to me that the notion of Objective Analysis in science is very relevent to > the consideration of evolution. do you believe that such a thing exists > (Objective Analysis), or do we simply get infinitely close? I do think "Objective Analysis" exists within the epistemological paradigm of "empirical methodology." In fact, it becomes a self-defined objective in the statement of the methodology. Such tautologies are common in philosophical systems. Perhaps this would be a good moment to switch the subject of the thread to one which is more directly pertinent to the list. To what degree did the Deism movement in the West provide an epistemological basis for the empirical study of evolution, as opposed to the idealistic one sanctioned by earlier theological traditions? We have all learned about the influence of William Paley and other Deistic theologians on the young Charles Darwin. How much influence did Deism have upon other scientists of the late 18th and 19th centuries? Morris Simon <msimon7@ua1ix.ua.edu> Stillman College _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:186>From ahouse@hydra.rose.brandeis.edu Tue Sep 21 12:55:46 1993 Date: Tue, 21 Sep 1993 14:02:24 -0500 To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu From: ahouse@hydra.rose.brandeis.edu (Jeremy John Ahouse) Subject: Re: Classification in mineralogy > Minerals are grouped together in two ways. The true >classification system is a tree, and is based on the chemistry >of the mineral. There are sulfides, sulfates, oxides and >silicates. The silicates are subdivided according to the SI:O >ratio. Further subdivisions occur on the grounds of structure, >and the finest distinctions are then made by chemical for- >mulae, with "subspecies" being solution series between >interchangeable atoms (example: % Fe vs Mg in a certain >crystal site). It isn't clear to me why this would necessarily generate a strictly dichotomous tree. If you had something that was 1/2 sulfide and 1/2 oxide where would it go? Thanks, - Jeremy _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:187>From huh@u.washington.edu Tue Sep 21 16:21:52 1993 Date: Tue, 21 Sep 1993 12:40:20 -0700 (PDT) From: Mark Rushing <huh@u.washington.edu> Subject: Re: A reply to Ramsden To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu On Tue, 21 Sep 1993, Morris Simon wrote: > You bet it's easy, Mark, as you can see from our current exchange. I think > we're talking about different things, or about the same thing from very > different perspectives. yes -- it's interesting -- and thank you for acknowledging multiple perspectives -- perhaps even the Subjective experience, to use a Categorical term. now maybe we can move somewhere... by the way, i'm very glad to hear from you again, non-categorically speaking, of course. > You speak of a "Power structure" [which] "is the > Tool we call Science." In fact, I simply spoke of pragmatics of empirical > science -- a "power structure" in C.P. Snow circles, perhaps, but not in > the ones most of my scientist colleagues and I move in. pragmatics (historically speaking) once Dictated that the earth was the center of the universe. i believe it was last year that this was admitted as a 'misunderstanding'. as out sense of pragmatics changed through the growing acceptance of Empiricism (dialectic?), the Old Hold On The Mind was forced to change -- to expand -- to encompass further horizons. this was a result of the inherent Power of Science. i believe it is important to acknowledge this Power. i am not attempting to reconcile academic disciplines, nor societal disparity. i speak only from my own being. but i don't want to wander too far from a pseudo-dialectic... i find the notion of Trees relevant when considering the methodological (Now, at least) 'progress' of science. Trees have branches, but there exists perhaps infinite space between the branches. many people adhere rigidly to their Disciplines. many people adhere rigidly to many things. this is fine, as long as we remember the 'spaces inbetween'. i'm wondering if this makes sense to you. when you speak here, as above when you Invoke the Snow image to encompass, or at least parallel what i am trying to say, you return to the notion of the ancient Cannon (Tradition). you link yourself in a group unit, a pack of Scientists banded together in Circles, moving within them. this is a power structure. it has effects. a old-boys network. a pristine framework of purely logical synthesis. it is their commonly held Image, their Icon, which exists externally from their individual being. this exerts a force in the world, like all groupings of minds. i am not a scientist. yet i have seen much of its effects. i enjoy the academics universal saying that there is good and bad in just about everything. but machines cannot weigh costs -- not necessarily in flesh and blood, but perhaps in what some might call Spirit (i mean nothing Theological) indulge me for a moment to waxe grandly -- Mother Church was a wild creature, heart, passion -- EXPAND, at all costs -- unite the west, cross boundaries -- irrational, driven by the winds and wholly unpredictable in its generosity, and in its horror. academia springs THROUGH her (in the west) and rational faculties previal. logic, reason, books, printing, this leads to that, leads to this, comes from that -- observe, analyze, categorize -- it left it's Mother behind. a whirling mechanism, shiny and razor sharp -- and it began slicing away at a very fat Mom. of course, that's not all science has done. but Science, not the Scientists, but rather the manifestation of Scientific 'progress' lacks a Spirit -- a Heart that can bleed. it was removed because it was not logical. i feel that although this is no new news, it is not yet Realised. you cannot write a computer progam to simulate a heart <-- metaphor, morris, not the actual Heart as Mechanism. population analysis (mean deviation) does it Relect or does it Shape? the implications of data on flesh. psychology -- aberrant behavior (thought) -- Institutionalize (or drug). Evolution -- heirarchy, some better than others? -- good question... Evolution -- only the STRONG will survive. only the most well-adapted. implications -- power and perhaps enlightening if you can figure out what you mean by well-adapted when considering societal parallels. anyway... sorry for spewing... > > when you say, "a person uses his/her cortex to modify sub-cortical > > perceptions" do you notice that Person is outside of his own mind? > > My clumsy way (science, not poetry) of distinguishing conscious thought > from unconscious physiological perception. whatever you mean by conscious and unconscious. i'm not so sure i accept that distinction. perhaps it will result in my being Institutionalized some day, who knows? > > large out there. it just bothered me that you were a rifle-toting > > Dialectician in an interdisciplinary setting. we have the opportunity to > > be so much more.... > > Ouch! That burned! Was that a bullet, or a red-hot synthesis? sorry, didn't mean it to hurt. but i AM very glad that you're trying to understand me. a lot of people who feel similarly are unable to express themselves well in Institutional terms. it's my not-humble-at-all opintion that the Institutions need to open their eyes and ears a little more to what goes on Beyond the Walls. > > end of appeal to the modern church. > > Amen. i lied.... > > to me that the notion of Objective Analysis in science is very relevent to > > the consideration of evolution. do you believe that such a thing exists > > (Objective Analysis), or do we simply get infinitely close? > > I do think "Objective Analysis" exists within the epistemological paradigm > of "empirical methodology." In fact, it becomes a self-defined objective in > the statement of the methodology. Such tautologies are common in > philosophical systems. Perhaps this would be a good moment to switch the > subject of the thread to one which is more directly pertinent to the list. > > To what degree did the Deism movement in the West provide an epistemological > basis for the empirical study of evolution, as opposed to the idealistic one > sanctioned by earlier theological traditions? We have all learned about > the influence of William Paley and other Deistic theologians on the young > Charles Darwin. How much influence did Deism have upon other scientists of > the late 18th and 19th centuries? tautologies!! thank you!! that reassures me immensely. i would like to know, also, how not only God influenced darwin (through human interpretations of perhaps human Ideals), but also why that is of any more significance, if it is, than how God, Deism, Flagellants, WHATEVER monotheistically-oriented Organization of thought, has influenced our Fundamental Foundations in Scientific thought. perhaps i should take this to some philosophical forum, but it seems a shame for philosophers to just talk amongst themselves when there's a whole petri dish full of cutting-edge scientists here. (sleight posturing to hopefully exploit an old Challenge instinct resulting in Disciplinary self-exploration concurrently with in Outsider's viewpoint) mark rushing post office box 85267 seattle, washington 98145-1267 206.329.8070 huh@u.washington.edu rushing@battelle.org Mark.Rushing@f157.n343.z1.fidonet.org _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:188>From mhallbey@magellan.geo.usherb.ca Tue Sep 21 18:20:30 1993 Date: Tue, 21 Sep 1993 19:20:07 -0400 From: mhallbey@magellan.geo.usherb.ca (Mryka Hall-Beyer) To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Subject: RE: Classification in mineralogy Interesting reply about minerals. I think we are defining "observable" in slightly different manners. I quite agree that a phenomenon such as colour is not appropriate in a classification scheme. Noting the colour or the range of possible colours or the most common colour of a mineral is useful in a rough identification key, but that is as far as it goes. I guess the fact that I work in remote sensing biases me into thinking of things as "observable" that are not accessible to our senses. The main "observable" bases underlying the standard mineralogical classification scheme are weight percents of the 14 or so most common elements, Si:O ratios, and crystallographic structure. The structure may be observable to the extent to which it influences crystal shape, but of course most minerals one sees do not have well-developed crystal faces. That's what makes mineral-hounding fun, trying to find those few that _do_ have such structure. The structure usually has to be observed using x-ray crystallography to be really sure. I find your ideas about persistence and process interesting. I had not thought of these concepts in relation to classification. Yet in some ways it is the process of mineralogical change that underlies metamorphic petrology. The question about chemical equilibria on various scales is crucial to using chemical mineralogy to interpret paleopressures and temperatures. The presence or absence of certain mineral species, or the state of transition between them, is how we define metamorphic isograds. My master's work looked at partitioning of Mg and Fe between coexisting minerals (on the mm scale) as a geobarometer. I'm not sure where this fits into your ideas - it just occurred to me as I read them and I thought I'd toss it out. Thanks for the discussion. Lurking around a different but kindred field gets the brain cranking! -Mryka _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:189>From mhallbey@magellan.geo.usherb.ca Tue Sep 21 18:58:38 1993 Date: Tue, 21 Sep 1993 19:58:12 -0400 From: mhallbey@magellan.geo.usherb.ca (Mryka Hall-Beyer) To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Subject: Re: Classification in mineralogy If you had something that was half sulfide and half oxide it would be two different minerals. If the sulfur were combined with the oxygen it would be a sulfate, which is another mineral altogether, on another tree branch. I'm not sure if I'm answering the question you're asking: if not, reply and I'll try again. Perhaps the problem is in the subdivision of minerals using the main anions or aions groups (not sure if that's a technical term, even if I had spelled it right!). The solution series, like the sub- stitutions of Fe for Mg, or of Al for Si for that matter, are among the cations of the formula. The cation content is not the basis for the main tree branches, but rather comes in farther along the branching when separating different minerals within the same anion group (sulfides, silicates, etc.). For example, a Mg pyroxene and an Fe pyroxene are two differently named minerals, end members of a solution series called pyroxenes. Pyroxenes are in turn a member of the silicates. An Mg oxide and an Fe oxide are not pyroxenes at all, since they are not silicates. You put silica in their formula and they turn into silicates, maybe pyroxenes if the structure is right. Interesting question. -Mryka _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:190>From @VTVM1.CC.VT.EDU:RMBURIAN@VTVM1.CC.VT.EDU Tue Sep 21 23:34:31 1993 Date: Wed, 22 Sep 93 00:18:34 EDT From: "Richard M. Burian" <RMBURIAN@VTVM1.CC.VT.EDU> Subject: John Langdon on heritability and cultural evolution To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu On September 20, replying to Holsinger, John Langdon wrote that he considered a trait to be heritable only if it involved a genetic or other biologically determined change. At least one standard account of heri- tability makes a trait heritable if there is higher [or, for that matter, different] correlation between parent and offsping than between random members of the parental and offspring generations. On such an account [which IS used in quantitative genetics!], (a) a heritable trait may not change over a long series of generations (e.g. if it remains at a selec- tively determined optimum), and (b) there is no requirement that the basis of the correlation be biological. Thus consider a stable dialect of a language. There is a higher correlation between parent and off- spring dialect than between random parental generation and random off- spring generation dialect. The trait is, on this definition, heritable. The dialect may [indeed, probably will] change with generational time, but that is not guaranteed by the definition of heritability. All of this removes one potential obstacle to theories of cultural evolution. But as Holsinger points out, without a serious account of mechanism of (cultural) evolutionary change, we don't really have such a theory. And as Rob Boyd and Pete Richerson argue in fairly interes- ting (first approximation) detail in _Culture and the Evolutionary Process_ (Chicago UP, 1985), no good theory of cultural evolution is likely unless it is a theory of the interaction of cultural and bio- logical evolution (the latter more narrowly conceived than the former) because of the interaction of quite different modes of inheritance. For reasons such as these, I happen not to be a fan of any of the theo- ries of cultural evolution at which I have glanced (I am NOT widely read in this area), but I want to argue against such (semi)apriori arguments blocking attempts to forge theories of cultural evolution such as the one about heritability put forward by Langdon. Richard Burian Science and Technology Studies, Virginia Tech rmburian@vtvm1.cc.vt.edu. _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:191>From DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Tue Sep 21 23:46:18 1993 Date: Tue, 21 Sep 1993 17:19:16 -0400 (EDT) From: DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Subject: "Witness" and "testimony" in the historical sciences To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Organization: University of NC at Greensboro In civil history our knowledge of past events is often based on the testimony of witnesses. By "witnesses" we ordinarily mean persons who observed the events in question. But the terms "testimony" and "witness" have been used for a very long time in the historical sciences with reference to _objects_ rather than persons. For example, one of the great popular geological works of the nineteenth century was Hugh Miller's _The Testimony of the Rocks_. (What does it mean to say that a rock "testifies"?) Students of textual transmission speak of the manuscript copies of a work -- the many different manuscript copies of the _Canterbury Tales_, for example -- as the "witnesses to the tradition" of that particular text. My questions are these: (1) How widely are these terms used in the historical sciences? Can anyone think of other examples of their use? When, for example, did textual scholars first start referring to individual manuscripts as "witnesses" to a tradition? (2) Are there any historical or theoretical analyses of the notions of "witness" and "testimony" as they apply to historical _objects_ rather than persons? I have seen one very interesting book called _Testimony: a Philosophical Study_ (C.A.J. Coady, 1993, Oxford University Press), but it is a work in the philosophy of law and is devoted exclusively to the testimony of persons. Bob O'Hara, Darwin-L list owner Robert J. O'Hara (darwin@iris.uncg.edu) Center for Critical Inquiry and Department of Biology 100 Foust Building, University of North Carolina at Greensboro Greensboro, North Carolina 27412 U.S.A. _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:192>From GANEVE@Vm1.rice.ucl.ac.be Wed Sep 22 07:48:18 1993 Date: Wed, 22 Sep 93 14:41:15 CET From: Gabriel NEVE <Neve@ecol.ucl.ac.be> Organization: Universite Catholique de Louvain Subject: TH & JS Huxley's Romanes lectures To: darwin-L@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu TH & JS Lectures entitled EVOLUTION AND ETHICS Dear Fellow Networkers, In 1893 Thomas Henry Huxley delivered, as an invited speaker at the "Romanes Lecture", a lecture on "Evolution and Ethics". Fifty years later, his grandson Julian was invited to celebrate the anniversary by giving a lecture with the same title, also at a "Romanes Lecture". Julian Huxley's lecture was published in 1946, together with his grandfather's lecture in a book. As this year marks the hundredth anniversary of TH Huxley's lecture, I wonder if this has been (or will be) celebratred in any way. By the way, does anybody know what the "Romanes Lectures" were (and, may be, still are)? I would welcome any information on follow ups from the Huxley's lectures. Gabriel ======================================================================= Gabriel NEVE Unite d'Ecologie et de Biogeographie EMAIL: NEVE@ECOL.UCL.AC.BE Universite de Louvain Croix du Sud 5 Fax : +32/10/473490 B-1348 Louvain-la-Neuve Tel : +32/10/473495 Belgium _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:193>From DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Wed Sep 22 10:10:12 1993 Date: Wed, 22 Sep 1993 10:51:54 -0400 (EDT) From: DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Subject: September 22 -- Today in the Historical Sciences To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Organization: University of NC at Greensboro SEPTEMBER 22 -- TODAY IN THE HISTORICAL SCIENCES 1711: THOMAS WRIGHT, author of _An Original Theory or New Hypothesis of the Universe, Founded upon the Laws of Nature, and Solving by Mathematical Principles the General Phaenomena of the Visible Creation; and Particularly the Via Lactea_, is born at Byers Green, near Durham, England. In his contemplation of cosmological time he will write: "In this great Celestial Creation, the Catastrophe of a World, such as ours, or even the total Dissolution of a System of Worlds, may possibly be no more to the great Author of Nature, than the most common Accident in Life with us, and in all Probability such final and general Doom-Days may be as frequent there, as even Birth-Days, or Mortality with us upon the Earth." (An Original Theory_, 1750, p. 76.) Today in the Historical Sciences is a feature of Darwin-L@ukanaix.cc. ukans.edu, a network discussion group on the history and theory of the historical sciences. E-mail darwin@iris.uncg.edu for more information. _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:194>From GA3704@SIUCVMB.SIU.EDU Thu Sep 23 09:33:19 1993 Date: Thu, 23 Sep 93 09:31:52 CST From: "Margaret E. Winters" <GA3704@SIUCVMB.SIU.EDU> To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Subject: interconnections Mark Rushing asked a couple of days ago about the interconnection between mental categories and, it seems to me, an even wider question about creativity. I don't know of any empirical studies (though surely there must be in the psychological literature - perhaps Eleanor Rosch is the place to start), but I can recommend a very good article which appeared in `Language' vol. 49 (1973) on abductive and deductive change, where its author, Henning Andersen, explores the nature of abductive reasoning, roughly the same as analogical thought. I've been thinking about the problem from the point of view of language change as well, and believe that the key lies here. Mark, I hope this gets you somewhere. Margaret Winters <ga3704@siucvmb.siu.edu> _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:195>From ahouse@hydra.rose.brandeis.edu Thu Sep 23 09:53:22 1993 Date: Thu, 23 Sep 1993 11:01:40 -0500 To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu From: ahouse@hydra.rose.brandeis.edu (Jeremy John Ahouse) Subject: alternate classifications ref I didn't see this book mentioned in our discussions of alternate categorizations and I wanted to pass it along. _Cognitive foundations of natural history - Toward and anthroplogy of science_ by Scott Atran. And thanks to all for the references back to Borges, it has little to do with the immediate discussion, but is wonderful to read. - Jeremy _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:196>From @KENTVM.KENT.EDU:SBROWN@KENTVM.KENT.EDU Thu Sep 23 11:33:08 1993 Date: Thu, 23 Sep 1993 12:29:07 -0500 (EST) From: Steven R Brown <SBROWN%KENTVM.BITNET@KUHUB.CC.UKANS.EDU> Subject: Re: interconnections To: Multiple recipients of list <darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu> On Thu, 23 Sep 1993 11:13:15 -0500 Margaret E. Winters said: >......................................... I can recommend >a very good article which appeared in `Language' vol. 49 >(1973) on abductive and deductive change, where its >author, Henning Andersen, explores the nature of abductive >reasoning, roughly the same as analogical thought.... To which I would add Andersen's "Perceptual and Conceptual Factors in Abductive Innovations," _Recent Developments in Historical Phonology_, 1978. _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:197>From huh@u.washington.edu Thu Sep 23 17:20:54 1993 Date: Thu, 23 Sep 1993 15:10:54 -0700 (PDT) From: Mark Rushing <huh@u.washington.edu> Subject: Re: interconnections To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu On Thu, 23 Sep 1993, Margaret E. Winters wrote: > author, Henning Andersen, explores the nature of abductive > reasoning, roughly the same as analogical thought. I've > been thinking about the problem from the point of view > of language change as well, and believe that the key lies > here. > Mark, I hope this gets you somewhere. thanks very much for the Direction, margaret -- it sounds like a very interesting path to follow for a while. i'm very curious about what you mean by language change. does it involve degrees of Abstraction, perhaps? by this i mean, and forgive me for being unfamiliar with linguistic terminology, as Knowledge grows within a society (and perhaps this is a very Western viewpoint), specific details are lumped into Categories (or new words which encompass 'greater' meaning) and people Evolve their language to a new 'level' of abstraction? this is particularly fascinating to me, as a wordsmith. it seem to allow a a good deal of room for Error, by losing the initial sub-elements of a Classification which created the Classification (or word) to begin with. mark rushing post office box 85267 seattle, washington 98145-1267 206.329.8070 huh@u.washington.edu rushing@battelle.org Mark.Rushing@f157.n343.z1.fidonet.org _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:198>From TREMONT%UCSFVM.BITNET@KUHUB.CC.UKANS.EDU Thu Sep 23 17:39:49 1993 Date: Thu, 23 Sep 1993 13:38:20 -0700 (PDT) From: "Elihu M. Gerson" <TREMONT%UCSFVM.BITNET@KUHUB.CC.UKANS.EDU> Subject: Heritability and cultural evolution To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu On Thu, 23 Sep 1993 09:59:32 -0500 Richard M. Burian said: >...At least one standard account of heri- >tability makes a trait heritable if there is higher [or, for that matter, >different] correlation between parent and offsping than between random >members of the parental and offspring generations. This way of looking at it puts us squarely in the middle of the ancient correlation-is-not-causaton discussion. Most usages of "heritability" (and similar terms that I've seen) assume or describe some causal connections between the characteristics of one generation and those of another, not just association. Correlations don't tell us anything about the cause of resemblances between parents and children. Thus, for example, if many people come down with an illness simultaneously, it may be impossible to determine from correlational data if the cause is contagion, heritable susceptibility, exposure to an irritant in the water supply, some combination of these, or something else altogether. > All of this removes one potential obstacle to theories of cultural >evolution. But as Holsinger points out, without a serious account of >mechanism of (cultural) evolutionary change, we don't really have such >a theory. True-- and we don't have any plausible theories of cultural evolution. Moreover, I think using the term "heritability" to refer to both biological and cultural transmission runs the risk of confusing processes which are very different in important respects. So I think we need a different term for the more general and abstract process which includes heritability on the one hand (i.e., biological transmission) and heritage or tradition (i.e., cultural transmission) on the other. And it will also be well to keep in mind that there are clearly many subkinds of each kind of transmission. I am particularly concerned to avoid arguments like: the contents of the second draft of my manuscript looks like the first draft of my manuscript, THEREFORE, keyboards (or maybe word processors) are what shapes the contents of manuscripts. Arguments of this form, in which lower-level (often genetic, often psychological) processes are awarded causal efficacy, and higher level (i.e., organizational, political) processes are ignored, are extremly common. They can be, and often are, used to justify the most terrible crimes, including genocide. So I think we should be very very clear in what we say and what we mean when we are dealing with these cross-level problems. I also think it is a good idea to keep in mind that the analysis of cross-level processes is very complex, and cannot be divided into a "so much of this, so much of that" way. Susan Oyama has done an outstanding analysis of nature-nurture controversies from this perspective: "The ontogeny of information", Cambridge U Press, 1985. Elihu M. Gerson Tremont Research Institute 458 29 Street San Francisco, CA 94131 415-285-7837 tremont@ucsfvm.ucsf.edu _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:199>From HOLSINGE@UCONNVM.BITNET Fri Sep 24 07:44:59 1993 Date: Fri, 24 Sep 1993 08:25:42 -0500 (EST) From: "Kent E. Holsinger" <HOLSINGE%UCONNVM.BITNET@KUHUB.CC.UKANS.EDU> Subject: Re: Heritability and cultural evolution To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Gerson makes a reasonable point in his reply to Burian. Using the term "heritability" to refer to both biological transmission and cultural transmission runs a risk. By failing to distinguish between them, on the basis of the _very_ different mechanisms underlying them, we may unwittingly make use of evolutionary principles that depend on biological heredity when trying to understand cultural evolution. It is important, however, to realize that there will be _some_ commonality between the processes, no matter how different the mechanisms underlying the transmission. Darwin's theory of natural selection, for example, requires only that offspring resemble their parents, i.e., that there is a _correlation_ between parental and offspring phenotypes. It does _not_ require any that any particular mode of transmission underly that correlation. In fact, Darwin got the mode of inheritance completely wrong. To the extent that we can make inferences about the characteristics of an evolutionary process from the fact of transmission alone, there are bound to be similarities between biological and cultural evolution. There are two aspects of cultural transmission that seem to have no counterpart in biological transmission (that I have been able to think of, at least). First, transmission isn't strictly unidirectional, from parent to offspring, in cultural transmission. Second, there is considerable horizontal transmission among individuals. Take attitudes towards homosexuality as an example. (I should note before proceeding that this entire discussion is based only on my _perception_ of attitudes, not on any actual data about them. Still, it serves to illustrate the point.) Attitudes among college-age students towards homosexuality seem clearly influenced by the environment in which they were raised, i.e., by their parents (at least in part). That's classical vertical transmission. However, students' attitudes are also influenced by the attitudes and behavior of their peers. I'm sure we all know of cases where a student who was adamantly anti-homosexual discovers that a friend is gay and, as a result, changes his attitude about homsexual behavior. (Of course, many times attitudes don't change.) That's an example of horizontal transmission. Similarly, parents sometimes change their attitudes about homosexual behavior as a result of learning that their son or daughter is gay/lesbian/bisexual. That's reverse vertical transmission. One of the significant questions in my mind is whether the extent of these alternative modes of transmission is so great that cultural and biological evolution share few interesting properties or if their extent is limited enough that there are significant similarities. Another is whether there are certain classes of cultural evolution, e.g., linguistic evolution, that are more similar to biological evolution than others, e.g., changes in sexual mores. -- Kent +--------------------------------------------------------------------+ | Kent E. Holsinger Internet: Holsinge@UConnVM.UConn.edu | | Dept. of Ecology & BITNET: Holsinge@UConnVM | | Evolutionary Biology, U-43 | | University of Connecticut | | Storrs, CT 06269-3043 | +--------------------------------------------------------------------+ _______________________________________________________________________________ <1:200>From mayerg@cs.uwp.edu Fri Sep 24 08:17:53 1993 Date: Fri, 24 Sep 1993 07:59:44 -0500 (CDT) From: Gregory Mayer <mayerg@cs.uwp.edu> Subject: Re: Heritability and cultural evolution To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu In his posting of 23 September, Elihu Gerson cautions us against using the one term heritability for both biological and cultural transmission, for while they are similar, calling them the same thing might obscure important differences. I would like to endorse his call for careful use of language and terminology in discussing these phenomena. While heritability could be expanded in meaning to include cultural transmission, it might well be best to restrict it to its well defined biological meaning. It is not quite right to define heritability (in the quantitative genetics sense), as Richard Burian has, as the correlation of parents and offspring. It is indeed true that parent/offspring correlation is a common experimental design for estimating heritability, but it is not the definition of heritability, nor the best experimental design. Heritability is defined as the proportion of the total variance among individuals (= the phenotypic variance) that is due to genetic variance among individuals. The phenotypic variance also has an environmental component, and the genetic variance can be further decomposed into additive, dominance and interaction components. More complex analyses of the variance to include further complications such as, e.g. genotype/environment correlation, are possible. The key point is that heritability is not just a correlation among parents and offspring (which can be similar for all sorts of reasons), but, by definition, a genetic (in the biological sense) phenomenon. Quantitative geneticists design their experiments so as to be able to estimate the various components, genetic and non-genetic, of the phenotypic variance. Thus if we were interested in the heritability of dialect, the first experiment a quantitative geneticist would think of would be to raise offspring from one dialect group in a different dialect group. Experiments much like this have been done to study song dialects of birds. If we did such an experiment with humans, we would find the heritability to be zero: an American child, raised from birth by a Brazilian family in Brazil, would speak Portuguese. The same, I would wager, would be true of dialects. There is, of course, an interesting cultural transmission of language in our American/Brazilian gedanken experiment, but it does not involve a non-zero quantitative genetic heritability. The second point worth mentioning about this is that heritabilty is an analysis of _variance_, i.e. of differences among individuals, and says nothing about mean values. If we did Richard Burian's study of heritability within a stable dialect, we would again find zero heritability. This time it would not be zero contingently, as in the case of the American child in Brazil (it _could_ have been the case that language was inherited genetically in man, as it is, in part, in some birds; it just happens that it isn't). It would in this case be zero by definition, because there would be no differences among individuals, since, by the setup of the example, they all spoke the same dialect. Again, there would be an interesting cultural transmission of language, but the quantitative genetic concept of heritability would not be a useful analytic tool. Heritability is a way of relating differences among individuals to differences in their genes, environment etc. Those interested in the details of heritability in the quantitative genetic sense should look at D.S. Falconer, 1989, _Introduction to Quantitative Genetics_, Longman, Harlow, Essex, and for an account of the limitations of this approach at R.C. Lewontin, 1974, The analysis of variance and the analysis of causes, _Amer. J. Hum. Gen._ 26:400-411. Gregory C. Mayer mayerg@cs.uwp.edu _______________________________________________________________________________ Darwin-L Message Log 1: 171-200 -- September 1993 End