rjohara.net |
Darwin-L Message Log 5: 41–70 — January 1994
Academic Discussion on the History and Theory of the Historical Sciences
Darwin-L was an international discussion group on the history and theory of the historical sciences, active from 1993–1997. Darwin-L was established to promote the reintegration of a range of fields all of which are concerned with reconstructing the past from evidence in the present, and to encourage communication among scholars, scientists, and researchers in these fields. The group had more than 600 members from 35 countries, and produced a consistently high level of discussion over its several years of operation. Darwin-L was not restricted to evolutionary biology nor to the work of Charles Darwin, but instead addressed the entire range of historical sciences from an explicitly comparative perspective, including evolutionary biology, historical linguistics, textual transmission and stemmatics, historical geology, systematics and phylogeny, archeology, paleontology, cosmology, historical geography, historical anthropology, and related “palaetiological” fields.
This log contains public messages posted to the Darwin-L discussion group during January 1994. It has been lightly edited for format: message numbers have been added for ease of reference, message headers have been trimmed, some irregular lines have been reformatted, and error messages and personal messages accidentally posted to the group as a whole have been deleted. No genuine editorial changes have been made to the content of any of the posts. This log is provided for personal reference and research purposes only, and none of the material contained herein should be published or quoted without the permission of the original poster.
The master copy of this log is maintained in the Darwin-L Archives (rjohara.net/darwin) by Dr. Robert J. O’Hara. The Darwin-L Archives also contain additional information about the Darwin-L discussion group, the complete Today in the Historical Sciences calendar for every month of the year, a collection of recommended readings on the historical sciences, and an account of William Whewell’s concept of “palaetiology.”
--------------------------------------------- DARWIN-L MESSAGE LOG 5: 41-70 -- JANUARY 1994 --------------------------------------------- DARWIN-L A Network Discussion Group on the History and Theory of the Historical Sciences _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:41>From abrown@independent.co.uk Sun Jan 9 07:12:26 1994 From: Andrew Brown <abrown@independent.co.uk> Date: Sat, 8 Jan 94 21:48:51 GMT To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Subject: Re: Langdon vs. Tuomistu, Brown and Occam's shaving foam Finn Rasmussen cheerfully admits to not having read Morgan's books: I'd rather he did so before having a go at her theory. I quite take his point about parsimonious explanations. That is what attracts me to her theory. At the core of it lies the observation that there are a number of human characteristics, of which the most obvious are aubcutaneous fat and the arrangement of our hair, which have many parallels among aquatic and shore-dwelling animals and none on the savannah. The most parsimonious explanation is surely that these are adaptations to a semi-aquatic mode of life. So far, I am still waiting for someone to put forward a more elegant explanation based on evolution a long way from water. Andrew Brown _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:42>From NEIMANF@YALEVM.CIS.YALE.EDU Sun Jan 9 07:40:17 1994 Date: Sun, 09 Jan 94 08:39:23 EST From: Fraser Neiman <NEIMANF@YaleVM.CIS.Yale.edu> Organization: Yale University C∧IS Subject: Re: Aquatic apes revisited To: Multiple recipients of list <darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu> Greetings, The old issue of how we evaluate scientific knowledge claims has surfaced again in the linguistic and aquatic ape threads on this list. I don't have anything novel to say on this topic. But perhaps it is worth pointing out that the discussion to date has a rather empiricist flavor. By that I mean that it fails to acknowledge that theories about the way the world works and, more to the point here, hypotheses about history that are constructed on the basis of those theories, are fundamentally underdetermined by facts (empirical evidence). I mention this not to suggest that there is no telling whether Renfrew or Morgan are right. I think there is. Rather I want to remind folks that the ability of an hypothesis to account for evidence in a parsimonious fashion is not the only criterion on which its worth is judged. The additional set of considerations, which often prove crucial, involves the fit of the hypothesis or theory with other theories or hypotheses about the way the world works. The continental drift case illustrates this nicely. The original formulation by Wegener did not win general acceptance NOT because it did not fit with the facts. It nicely fit all kinds of facts, including the complementary shapes of the continental margins and agreement in the distribution of fossils and geological formations on opposing shores. But it did not fit with other theoretical notions about the way the geophysical world worked. It offered no theoretical mechanism. The invention of plate tectonics remedied this defect and acceptance quickly followed. The "consilience of inductions" runs in two directions, one empirical and the other theoretical. I wonder if this goes some way to explaining the difficulties that Morgan encounters among card-carrying paleoanthropologists, and the ensuing lack of resolution between the professionals and the outsiders. Although the argument is conducted in terms of "facts" much of the professional position arises from an unarticulated lack of agreement between the hypothesis and the rest of their understanding about Plio-Pleistocene hominoid evolution and evolution in general. For example one thing that strikes me about the aquatic ape hypothesis is that it is a "functional package" explanation. It attempts to explain a large suite of traits in terms of positive feedback linkages among them in the context of a single selective prime mover. Now this kind of explanation has an long history in paleoanthropology, most conspicuously in the hands-tools-reduced- canines-brain-bipedalism package that goes right back to Darwin. Scientific progress in paleoanthroplogy over the last 25 year has, to a large extent, consisted in uncoupling the traits in this package. More generally, we have come to understand that evolutionary histories caused by natural selection are quirky and historically contingent processes. Morgan's functional package runs afoul of this more general understanding. Clearly historical linguists have a similar kinds of problems with Renfrew. But the bi-directional consilience argument cuts both ways in this case. European history happened only one way. The question is how did it happen? We are going to have a much better chance of getting it right, if we follow the lead of Renfrew, Cavalli-Sforza, Ammerman, et al. and begin seriously to look for inductive consilience among historical hypotheses constructed from theory in different disciplines. The unfortunate tendency is for practitioners in archaeology and linguistics to send immediately for the game warden and have the poachers hauled off the estate. I think a more profitable attitude might be to recognize that the correct interpretation of the archaeological and linguistic records is going to have to agree with the correct interpretation of the genetic record, and vice versa. This does not mean that Cavalli et al. are right. I think they _have_ pointed the way to an important methodological opportunity. Although they may not have exploited it in an entirely satisfactory fashion. Best, Fraser Neiman _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:43>From ad201@freenet.carleton.ca Sun Jan 9 09:35:59 1994 Date: Sun, 9 Jan 1994 10:39:20 -0500 From: ad201@freenet.carleton.ca (Donald Phillipson) To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Subject: Method Bayla Singer (bsinger@eniac.seas.upenn.edu) wrote Jan 8 |Mike salovesh raises the question of how to deal with what might be called |'inspired guesses.' |Well, how do we deal with, e.g., Lucretius and atomic theory? | |The ideal (normative?) way is to accept an idea as a hypothesis until |it is rigorously proven by accepted methods. Coming back to Wegener: |I clearly remember gazing, in my elementary school years (late 1940s), |at the map of the world and thinking how well South America would fit |into Africa, etc. How much credit should I get, who not only didn't |publish, but had not the foggiest idea that I should even -think- |about a way such movement could possibly have happened? | |We can take my daydreams as one end of a spectrum: Wegener and the |brilliant-guesser linguists went further, but in the judgement of |their disciplinary peers not quite far enough. You suggest the plausible but now discarded idea that the process of creation/invention (i.e. thinking a genuinely novel thought) and the process of proof (that it is true) are or ought to be related. Repeated empirical failures have led to most scholars abandoning the proposition. The historical record suggests no no one gets credit for sheer originality. Credit comes for "making a contribution" i.e. integrating the novel idea with the rest of the discipline, or else for solving disciplinary problems. Being right is (usually) necessary but not sufficient. Inspired guesses that do not integrate with at least some other knowledge are a non-category. The classic example is Velikovsky's guess that Venus was hot when astronomers thought it was cold. (1) He could not provide data or reasoning to show why he might be right (and he was right); (2) His proposition Venus=hot could not be linked to the rest of planetary science at that date. So he was right, but his "contribution to science" was zero. Atomism in Lucretius' day was an interesting but philosophical idea -- not a "disciplinary topic" or a "research problem" in any branch of what we now call science. (It became a disciplinary topic only for Newton and a research problem in 1800, cf. Dalton.) Continental drift was in 1910 probably scorned because it was too simple to be plausible, but no less because it solved no current problem in geophysics -- even though "problems" in narrative sciences like palaeontology and geophysics are much less clearly demarcated than in experimental sciences like chemistry. When Wegener suggested South America fitted into Africa, he got no credit because he was proposing a true solution to what had not yet become a disciplinary problem. When you were daydreaming the identical idea, you were not at "one end of a spectrum" with geophysicists. You were not a player in their game, so no one would have accepted your idea (if published) even as a hypothesis. | There were many incandescent |electric light bulbs developed before Edison's, and he himself |developed many improvements afterward, to the point where it is |extremely difficult for the knowledgeable historian to say "this is |'the' light bulb patent." There was only one equally bright and long-lasting lamp, Joseph Swan's, a year earlier. Whether "knowledgeable" or not, the discipline-oriented historian has to define `the' in terms of the current discipline, rather than in terms of either Edison or novelty. Her criteria might be launching an industry that did not exist before, providing the commercial or material basis for a new technology, reducing house fires (from gas lamps) etc. Good criteria could also be used elsewhere in the discipline, to identify `the' critical invention in mediaeval warfare or aviation or city planning. This is the ideal/normative view. However, like all the humanities and social sciences, the discipline of history is not under the material or social constraints that make the natural sciences both uniquely productive and 99% unanimous in their conclusions. Linguistics is obviously polyvalent like the social sciences, not convergent like astronomy, physics, chemistry, etc. (Scope for a serious debate here, whether (1) all disciplines are on the same "spectrum" with experimental physics at one end and sociology at the other, or (2) humanities and social sciences are a (or two) species different from the natural sciences, and should not be allowed to claim the NS's privileges, e.g. that discoveries in one field (say linguistics) are likely to apply in another (say sociology.) None of this means we don't need inspiration, guesses, etc. But we need not waste time looking for parallels between methods of discovery (or original invention) and methods of proof (that something is true). Part of what makes history of science fascinating is the prospect of discovering more about both invention and proof. -- | Donald Phillipson, 4050 Hall's Road, Carlsbad | | Springs, Ont., Canada K0A 1K0; tel: (613) 822-0734 | | "What I've always liked about science is its independence from | | authority"--Ontario Science Centre (name on file) 10 July 1981 | ------------------------------ Cut here ------------------------------ _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:44>From DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Sun Jan 9 12:50:56 1994 Date: Sun, 09 Jan 1994 13:56:56 -0400 (EDT) From: DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Subject: Arguments in science To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Organization: University of NC at Greensboro The following comes to us from Peter Stevens (p_stevens@nocmsmgw.harvard.edu). Bob O'Hara (darwin@iris.uncg.edu) --------------------------------- As we work through arguments about aquatic apes, over-optimistic ornithologists and lapsed linguists, we may take heart from, or despair over, the case of William Sharp Macleay. Proponent of the ultimately discarded idea of Quinarianism, he acknowledged that he might well be wrong, but that progress in the discipline would result from the activities of those who disproved his thesis as being false (I am sorry, I do not have the text here). The botanist A.-H. G. de Cassini made a similar comment about -his- ideas. And of course the arguments Macleay stirred up were integral to the distinction between analogy and affinity. Also, the number of people who refer to Macleay's ideas directly or indirectly is quite large (as far as I know, no study had been carried out). Finally, if you want a good example of ad hominem arguments in particular, and pure vituperation in general, read some of Macleay's papers... Of course, one might reply to Macleay, was it really -necessary- for change that we should have had to spend time and energy in disproving your ideas? Hull's discussion (in "Science as a Process") about over how to use developmental data in deciding on which characters were advanced and which primitive is perhaps relevant here. Lundberg withdrew from the debate, and so could be seen as leaving the field to Nelson. However, I cannot see that the numerous papers addressing the question over the next decade or more led to that much clarification of the argument. I am also reminded of the story of Paul Mangelsdorf, a central figure in developing our knowledge of corn (maize) breeding, who is said to have complained how much effort it had taken him in disproving the suggestion that Edgar Anderson (an ideas man) had made almost in passing that maize was known in SE Asia before it could have been arrived there aided by europeans. There is no real conclusion to all this, except that life would be very boring without any arguments! At the same time, there has to be balance within a discipline between people who push ideas on shaky or no data, theoreticians, fact-gatherers who disdain theory (of course, they are likely to be subtly, but no less deeply in thrall to unarticulated theories), etc. Perhaps I am wrong, but for all our discussion, we do not seem to be that much closer in prescribing the optimal situation for change in science. P. F. Stevens. _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:45>From WILLS@macc.wisc.edu Sun Jan 9 16:53:37 1994 Date: Sun, 09 Jan 94 16:54 CDT From: Jeffrey Wills <WILLS@macc.wisc.edu> Subject: Re: Greenberg and other controversial beliefs To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu I want to thank Bob O'Hara for suggesting Sibley as a parallel for Greenberg. At the heart of the matter, I think, is the same methodological problem with these "Buckshot Methods": not that the method is controversial or eccentric, but that there is no method. No method, by which I mean no one besides these inspired few could reproduce the same results. And yet why are his "results" of such interest to certain anthropologists and others? In the case of Greenberg (I cannot speak for Sibley), I think the method works this way: 1) you start with the fruits of the discipline's work. You don't challenge demonstrated connections, but try to move on to new terrain. What G. observes from past work is that--golly gee gosh--most language families are contiguous. 2) Taking this insight of contiguity (never expressed nor perhaps realized consciously) G. hypothesizes super-families. How does this hypthothesis arise? Because of substantial work making lots of little connections between families? No--that hardly exists. Rather Greenberg's search for superfamilies is theory-driven rather than data-driven (as Wegener might have been). Of course, Greenberg is not starting entirely from scratch: he has Sapir's six superstocks for North America and the undemonstrated hypothesis of other big groupers. In fact, so far G. has done nothing new-- unless he would actually try to argue/prove his supergroups. This leads to: 3) A naked theory without data is a public scandal. Lest he be arrested for indecent exposure (and because he genuinely believes in these superfamilies) G. looks for cognates in these hypothesized kin. It is as this stage that the points of Victor Golla and others about probability in sets of large random data take over. G's method is really one of randomness; with unlabeled data sets I think he would/could create entirely different families. In fact Lyle Campbell (Language 64.606-9) elegantly plays G's game ("method" would be to misunderstand the matter) and finds striking matches of Penutian (one of G's West Coast assemblages) and Finnish. It is at this stage that Greenberg makes his "contribution". But alas, Campbell documents frequent significant problems with G's data in practically every category you can name: sound-and-meaning isomorphism, borrowing, semantics, unmatched segments, onomatopoeia, lack of grammatical similarities, distributional oddities, repeated cognates, false cognates, erroneous reconstructions, erroneous morphological analysis and even spurious forms. It's obvious that G. enjoys matching up words in dictionaries (a harmless sport) but to pretend he is engaged in linguistics without good knowledge of his data set is not so harmless. To return to my question: why do the results of this non-method method appeal to others in anthropology or genetics? Because G's "results" are really nothing more than his assumptions: that people living near each other once spoke the same language (let's call them Group A) and that group B next to Group A must have originally spoken the same language (supergroup AB) etc. Remember that Greenberg's main thesis in Lang.in Am.(p. 38) is that "all the languages of the Americas, except those of the Na-Dene and Eskimo-Aleut groups, fall into a single vast assemblage." G's "breakthrough" is to demonstrate the linguistic unity of a large hemispheric group who naturally share overlaps in culture and genetics. How can you go wrong? In fact, I should have preceded this message by a sample poll of the non-linguists on Darwin-L: How many of you think all the languages in the Americas are ultimately related to each other? Thinking that "Amerindian" is ultimately united is hardly counter-intutitive because in fact it is the linguistic expression of a non-linguistic assumption (neighbors are related). In one sense the real achievement of linguistics has been to identify surprising, non-adjacent language groups (Finno-Ugric, or the connection of Yurok and Wiyot on the West Coast to the rest of the Algonquin family). In reference to the comments on the profit of controversial theories, remember that Greenberg's classification in essence has been known since 1956 and has neither won acceptance nor stimulated any significant research. Alternative Theories for REALLY BIG LANGUAGE FAMILIES. It has been reasonably suggested several times on this list that the best way to drive out Folly is to ignore it and promote Truth instead. But here is my dilemma (although other linguists on this list may wish to give me reason for hope): I don't think we will ever have the data we need to answer these questions about languages more than a few thousand years before their documentation. Language mutates at a sufficiently fast rate that there is very little embedded in it which gives evidence of its origins after a few thousand years. Unlike anthropologists who can hope to discover cultural artifacts or palaeologists who can hope to discover fossils and use genetic analysis, we have no reason to think there was any recorded language (and certainly not a significant amount of it) much earlier than we have found it (dates varying by region). I think the SuperGrouper language game is like asking: "What was the origin and the subsequent historical distribution of marriage rites?" A fascinating question, which we will never stop asking, for which we have contemporary cross-cultural evidence galore. We can even think it likely that all hominids had mating rites or that there was monogenesis or polygenesis of such rites and we can even hope to discover a few artifacts which we might plug into these theories, but to graph a full "tree" of marriage rites or language or other evanescent facets of human culture would need whole new categories of evidence. Anyone out there with the Great Galactic Sonograph should please speak up. Perhaps I have a bad attitude, but given this data deficit, how would you suggest we try to advance alternative theories for matters on which we have no evidence or even reasonable expectation of evidence? Sincerely, Melancholy in Madison. Jeffrey Wills wills@macc.wisc.edu _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:46>From DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Sun Jan 9 18:56:18 1994 Date: Sun, 09 Jan 1994 20:02:19 -0400 (EDT) From: DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Subject: A positive and workable idea for the historical linguists To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Organization: University of NC at Greensboro Dear Melancholy in Madison: A couple of comments first, and then a positive idea. It does seem to be a difference between systematics and historical linguistics that the linguists will sometimes claim that certain major language families are either not historically related, or that the evidence that they are can never be recovered. Systematists, in contrast, tend to assume that everything is related (there is only one tree of life), and that it's just a matter of figuring out what these historical relationships are. That being the case, it may be difficult for some of the systematists to understand criticism of Greenberg et al. on the grounds of non-relationship of the languages, because it is one of the routine assumptions of our field that "non-relationship" doesn't really exist; it's all a matter of more and less close relationship. The geographic points (which I was quite pleased to see) also tend to run counter to our common assumptions. This is _not_ to say that we are right and the linguists are wrong; it is only by way of pointing out how each of our disciplines is inclined to approach the problem. Wallace wrote a classic paper in 1855, as he was trying to develop his ideas on evolution, in which he proposed what is now usually called "Wallace's Law": "Every species has come into existence coincident in both space and time with a pre-existing closely allied species." But now a positive idea in response to Victor's original question of what the non-specialists would like to see from the historical linguists; things that might promote the field as a whole. What I would like to see is a large wall chart, maybe three or four feet square, professionally done, that illustrates the history of the Indo-European languages. I could and would use such a chart in some of my courses in evolutionary biology to show the parallels between the two fields, and maybe some of the linguistics societies could get together and promote this as a great thing for school and college classrooms. What this chart should show is PIE at the root, with a list of sample words alongside the root, and as you go up the tree the changes in these words are traced (numerals, kinship terms, etc.). Thus when I look at the tips of the branches I would see the selected words in English, French, Russian, etc., and would be able to trace back all of their transformations. This chart should be packed with information, and should not bejust a sketch. In the corners you could have a simplified version of the tree imposed on a map to show migration routes. The main tree will of course have some reticulation in it, representing borrowing, etc. (When I use the word "tree" I don't mean something that is rigidly bifurcating; I just mean a genealogical diagram that shows an estimate of the history. If some of that history is reticulate that's fine; it's still mostly a tree.) The French branch, for example, would have a set of dotted lines crossing over to the English branch around the time of the Norman Conquest, and this would carry indications of the types of language elements that were most likely to be transferred and the ones that were most likely to remain unaltered. It would take a lot of work to produce such a chart, but I think it would be well worth it from the view of both pedagogy and proselytizing. Put this chart in every elementary and high school classroom where an Indo-European language is spoken, and pretty soon there'll be more little historical linguists running around than you'll know what to do with. ;-) If such a chart in fact already exists, I want to know about it. I make the above suggestion in the knowledge that I should be able to give you an equivalent chart showing, say, the phylogeny of the vertebrates, but I cannot. This is something on my list of someday-projects. Smithsonian Press publishes a not-so-great chart of animal evolution. The real models to follow for style and professionalism are the geologic time scales you can get from Cambridge University Press, for example, or professionally done periodic tables of elements. The Cambridge geologic time scale is $14.95, and comes nicely folded in a sturdy plastic envelope (ISBN 0-521-39880-0). Just right. Bob O'Hara, Darwin-L list owner Robert J. O'Hara (darwin@iris.uncg.edu) Center for Critical Inquiry and Department of Biology 100 Foust Building, University of North Carolina at Greensboro Greensboro, North Carolina 27412 U.S.A. _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:47>From GOLLAV@axe.humboldt.edu Sun Jan 9 18:58:40 1994 Date: Sun, 9 Jan 1994 17:04 PST From: GOLLAV@axe.humboldt.edu Subject: Greenberg & Renfrew (one last time) To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu One final posting on Greenberg and Renfrew, and then I promise to hold my peace. Donald Phillipson writes: > The historical record suggests no one gets credit for sheer > originality. Credit comes for "making a contribution" i.e. integra- > ting the novel idea with the rest of the discipline, or else for > solving disciplinary problems. Being right is (usually) necessary > but not sufficient. Inspired guesses that do not integrate with at > least some other knowledge are a non-category. And Fraser Neiman writes: > The unfortunate tendency is for practitioners in archaeology and > linguistics to send immediately for the game warden and have the > poachers hauled off the estate. I think a more profitable attitude > might be to recognize that the correct interpretation of the archaeo- > logical and linguistic records is going to have to agree with the > correct interpretation of the genetic record, and vice versa. This > does not mean that Cavalli et al. are right. I think they _have_ > pointed the way to an important methodological opportunity. Although > they may not have exploited it in an entirely satisfactory fashion. Phillipson's observation holds for Greenberg, Renfrew, and for others of their ilk, EVEN IF they are "pointing the way to an important methodo- logical opportunity. As the Wegener case shows, even a well-argued and potentially productive hypothesis can still fail to "make a contribution" if it does not cross the threshold of connectedness with the body of already accepted hypotheses at the time. Greenberg and Renfrew are egregiously short on such connectivity. I regret the following ad hominem remarks, but it is necessary to make them to show this particular problem in the clearest light. The root cause of Renfrew's and Greenberg's failure to gain acceptance for their ideas -- Cavalli Sforza is another matter -- is that they are lazy. They have indeed glimpsed certain possibilities and syntheses. But they have laid their work on the table in the shoddiest of states, with little attention to the historical details as they are understood by informed specialists. Scott DeLancey and Jeffrey Wills have already described Greenberg's sins of ommission and commission in the comparative vocabularies of _Language in the Americas_. Let me cite a typical gaffe of Renfrew's. In the article he published in the January issue of _Scientific American_, he explains the dispersal of the "Na-Dene" language stock as one of the "climate-related dispersals" of the late Holocene. By this he means that, like the expansion of the Eskimo-Aleuts along the Arctic coast, or of other language families in Siberia, the Na-Dene expansion was probably motivated by the opening up of an ecological niche on the northern periphery of human settlement. The initial Na-Dene dispersal, he believes, represents "an early adaptation to the tundra environment." -- Plausible enough to the non-specialist, but the "Na-Dene" language family is a historic relationship linking Athabaskan, Eyak, and Tlingit (some--including Greenberg--also add Haida). Of these Na-Dene subgroups, only Athabaskan has a "tundra" location; the other languages are deeply entrenched in Northwest Coast environments. Renfrew presumably derives the latter from the former, by social mechanisms unspecified. While the origins of Northwest Coast populations are far from clear (here is where genetics may have a lot to say), this is certainly not the most likely scenario. This, however, is a small embarrassment compared to what comes next. To explain the wide dispersal of Athabaskan speech communities throughout much of Western North America -- including enclaves on the Pacific coast of Oregon and California as well as the Navajo and Apache of the Southwest -- Renfrew invokes another mechanism, "elite dominance," by which he means military conquest and similar agressive expansions of populations. I cite the passage in full (p.120): > Later, when climate or ecological factors rendered the area [i.e., > the "tundra"] less hospitable to them, they moved south. Some speakers > of Proto-Na-Dene penetrated as far as Arizona and New Mexico. Elite > dominance, amplified by horeseback riding, accounts for the presence > of the cultures related to this language group throughout much of the > continent. This howler, I think, gives the game away. Renfrew is so profoundly ignorant of North American culture history that he believes (a) that the Athabaskan expansion of ca. 700-1200 AD was part of the "Proto-Na-Dene" expansion of 2000 to 2500 years earlier (to cite the usual glottochronological estimates); and (b) that this was accomplished by Genghis-Khan-like mounted horse warriors, when every schoolchild, at least in the United States, knows that the horse was brought to the Western Hemisphere by Europeans after 1492. In other words, Renfrew couldn't be bothered to look up some elementary facts in a desk encyclopedia before commiting his "new synthesis" to writing in a journal that has a circulation in the millions. The sad truth is, both Renfrew and Greenberg have taken advantage of their considerable seniority (both Renfrew and Greenberg are well past 60 and heaped with academic honors) to publish and publicize some half-baked, overweening claims to significant breakthroughs. In so doing, they have not only failed to gain acceptance for what might well be "true" hypotheses, but have brought a certain odor of disrepute on the whole enterprise of interdisciplinary prehistory. Historical science must be cumulative, and new hypotheses and syntheses must work hard to integrate with previous schemata. Historical facts will not go away or change their color to suit the integrating fad of the day, and most of the hypotheses we work with in one generation will be equally "true" (or "false") in the next. A meaningful and productive marriage of genetics, archaeology, and historical linguistics can only be the product of years of research, by teams of researchers confident of the worth of the enterprise and respectful of every shard of data. Arrogant balderdash, promulgated largely in a journalistic mode, cannot speed this process, and may indeed significantly retard it by stirring the anger and resentment of the very individuals on whose specialized work it must build. Victor Golla Humboldt State University Arcata, California 95521 gollav @ axe.humboldt.edu _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:48>From DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Mon Jan 10 00:20:18 1994 Date: Mon, 10 Jan 1994 01:26:18 -0400 (EDT) From: DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Subject: January 10 -- Today in the Historical Sciences (*Special Edition*) To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Organization: University of NC at Greensboro JANUARY 10 -- TODAY IN THE HISTORICAL SCIENCES (*SPECIAL EDITION*) 1794 (200 years ago today): JOHANN GEORG ADAM FORSTER, Anglo-German natural historian, geographer, anthropologist, and illustrator, dies at Paris, France. This special edition of Today in the Historical Sciences commemorates the bicentennial of Forster's death, and reproduces the complete sketch of his career by Michael E. Hoare from the _Dictionary of Scientific Biography_. Forster, who sailed around the world on the _Resolution_ with James Cook from 1772 to 1775, might be pleased to know that tonight he is making the circuit again, this time through a network of wires at the speed of light. [Johann Georg Adam] Forster was the oldest son of Johann Reinhold Forster and Justina Elisabeth Forster. A precocious child, he was first educated by his father and acquired from him a lively and practical interest in natural history, as well as a thorough grounding in the numerous philological disciplines and languages which Johann Reinhold had mastered. In 1765 he accompanied his father on the survey of the German colonies on the Volga steppes and, for a short period while in Russia, attended the Petrisschule founded by the eminent geographer A. F. Busching. In 1766 he went to England with his father and in 1767 published his first work, a translation of M. V. Lomonosov's history of Russia. By the age of thirteen he had a command of most of the major languages of Europe. While his father was in Warrington, Lancashire, Forster was apprenticed to a merchant in London. In the autumn of 1767 he joined his father at the Dissenters' Academy, where he continued his own studies and assisted with the instruction. He also aided his father in the translation of Bougainville's _Voyage autour du monde_. When the elder Forster received the commission to sail on Cook's second voyage (1772-1775), he insisted that his son accompany him as assistant and artist. Afterward the younger Forster published his first major work, _A Voyage Round the World_ (London, 1777). As a result of this work, issued without official sanction, Forster became engaged in a spirited polemic with William Wales, the astronomer on the voyage, over the ethics of publishing an independent narrative in defiance of the Admiralty. The _Voyage_, although deliberately lacking the systematic and scholarly presentation of geographic and scientific material found in his father's _Observations_, started a new genre ably developed later by Alexander von Humboldt, whom Forster influenced greatly by his work and ideas. In 1776 the Forsters issued _Characteres generum plantarum_, and in 1777 the younger Forster was elected a fellow of the Royal Society. Although his preference was to continue his studies in England, Forster was forced by his family's circumstances to seek positions for himself and his father in Germany, and in 1779 he was appointed professor of natural history at the Collegium Carolinium in Kassel. He was soon in contact with the prominent men of science and letters in Germany, including J. F. Blumenbach, G. C. Lichtenberg, and S. T. Sommering. Forster was particularly attracted by the intellectual climate of Gottingen. In 1784 he was appointed to the chair of natural history at Vilna, Poland, and the following year he married Therese Heyne, daughter of the eminent Gottingen philologist C. G. Heyne. Forster collaborated with Lichtenberg in editing and writing the _Gottingisches Magazin der Wissenschaften und Litteratur_, and he also published extensively in the _Gottingische Anzeigen von gelehrten Sachen_. In Vilna, although isolated from the mainstream of European thought, Forster strove to correspond with men of science throughout Europe. In 1786 he published his M.D. dissertation (conferred by Halle), _De plantis esculentis insularum Oceani Australis commentatio botanica_ (Berlin-Halle) and _Florulae insularum Australium prodromus_ (Gottingen). The latter work was seen by Forster as the basis for a more comprehensive botanical work on the Pacific area, the "Icones plantarum in itinere ad insulas Maris Australis...." He also intended to publish a major study of European exploration in the Pacific. In 1787 Forster published at Gottingen _Fasciculas plantarum Magellanicarum_ and _Plantae Atlanticae_. J. D. Hooker, in his later work on the botany of the _Erebus_ and _Terror_ voyages, drew critically on the work of the Forsters, who in turn were indebted to Daniel Solander, Cook's _Endeavour_ botanist. Apart from his botanical work Forster's main contributions to the natural history of Cook's second voyage were his drawings and, later, his philosophical and geographic essays. In 1786 he engaged in a polemic with Kant over his theory of the origins of man. In 1787, prevented by war from taking up an appointment as naturalist to a Russian expedition, Forster returned to Gottingen; and in October 1788 he was appointed librarian at the University of Mainz. Between March and July 1790, accompanied by Humboldt, he traveled to England via the Rhineland and the Low Countries. His most important prose work, _Ansichten vom Niederrhein_ (Berlin, 1791-1794), was a penetrating account of his journey with Humboldt. During the Mainz period his interest and writing turned more to social history and politics. He became absorbed in the French administration which governed Mainz from October 1792. In March 1793, Forster went as a Rhineland deputy to the National Convention in Paris, where he died of illness aggravated by scurvy contracted during the _Resolution_ voyage. Forster wrote of himself in 1789: "Natural science in its broadest sense and particularly anthropology have been my occupation hitherto. What I have written since my voyage is closely related to that." Cook's voyages opened up new areas of investigation to men of science in Europe. Forster, the universal scholar, was a remarkable apologist for the new era of scientific discovery. Fully alive to all the great movements of his day and in contact with the most eminent men in Germany and abroad, Forster, who had been well schooled by his father, did much to convey to the parochial world of German science and letters the significance of the great contemporary advances in the geographic and biological sciences -- in some of which disciplines German-speaking scientists were destined to have a profound influence in the ensuing century. Michael E. Hoare in the _Dictionary of Scientific Biography_ (New York). Today in the Historical Sciences is a feature of Darwin-L, an international network discussion group on the history and theory of the historical sciences. For more information about Darwin-L send the two-word message INFO DARWIN-L to listserv@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu, or gopher to rjohara.uncg.edu (152.13.44.19). _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:49>From abrown@independent.co.uk Mon Jan 10 04:22:39 1994 From: Andrew Brown <abrown@independent.co.uk> Date: Mon, 10 Jan 94 09:40:00 GMT To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Subject: Re: Greenberg and other controversial beliefs I'd just like to thank Jeffrey Wills for a post which makes very clear to non-specialists a specialist's objections. Andrew Brown _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:50>From PLHILL@Augustana.edu Mon Jan 10 14:32:55 1994 From: PLHILL@Augustana.edu Organization: Augustana College - Rock Island IL To: <darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu> Date: Mon, 10 Jan 1994 14:34:57 GMT-500 Subject: parsimony Finn Rasmussen claims that parsimonious hypotheses must also be the least fantastic. This is clearly a mistake. Copernicus' geokinetic universe was arguably (not certainly) more parsimonious than its geostatic competitors. It was also far more fantastic in its implications, chiefly in the physics of motion. One can easily imagine circumstances in which belief in ghosts would afford the most parsimonious explanation of various puzzling phenomena. The hypothesis might still be rejected precisely because it is fantastic, meaning (roughly) that it is so difficult to integrate with the rest of what we believe. Rasmussen is also wrong about the Church's attitude toward geocentrism. It did not prefer this theory because its "centrism" mirrored Church structures. Copernicus was also a centrist, a solar centrist, and that would have done just as well so far as theocratic politics was concerned. Even if this had been the Church's motivation, why does Rasmussen think this would make the alternative "unscientific" or (much more absurdly) "dangerous?" There is no obvious reason why political and/or religious analogies should always be useless to science. David K. Hill Augustana College Rock Island, IL _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:51>From J_LIMBER@UNHH.UNH.EDU Mon Jan 10 16:28:42 1994 Date: Mon, 10 Jan 1994 17:30:38 -0500 (EST) From: J_LIMBER@UNHH.UNH.EDU (JOHN LIMBER) Subject: seeking examples of "train of thought" metaphor To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu I'm looking for metaphoric uses (or criticisms) of the expression "train of thought" in regard to human consciousness and language and would appreciate any examples anyone might be aware of or come across. Below are some examples to give you an idea of what I'm looking for. Darwin--to take an example relevant to this list--used this phrase in his discussion of the origin of language (1) and remarks on consciousness and habit (2). Others using it include Reid (3) and Hobbes (4). (Don't assume I already know anything! I've just begun thinking about this systematically and any ideas, interpretations or leads would be appreciated.) Thanks, John Limber, psychology, University of New Hampshire ************* (1)"As the voice was used more and more, the vocal organs would have been strengthened and perfected through the principle of the inherited effects of use...but the relation between the continued use of language and development of the brain, has no doubt been far more important....we may confidently believe that the continued use and advancement of this power would have reacted on the mind itself, by enabling it and encouraging it to carry on long trains of thought." (Origins, 1871) (2) "The possibility of two quite separate trains going on in the mind as in double consciousness may really explain what habit is... (M notebook) (3)"Such trains of thought discover themselves in children about two years of age...I think we may perceive a distinction between the faculties of children two or three years of age and those of the most sagacious brutes." (Reid, 1812/1969) (4) ""By the Trayne of Thoughts I understand that succession of one thought to another...to distinguish it from Discourse in Words." (Hobbes, 1651) _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:52>From hantuo@utu.fi Mon Jan 10 18:28:22 1994 To: Darwin-L@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu From: hantuo@utu.fi (Hanna Tuomisto) Subject: re: DARWIN-L digest 115 Date: Tue, 11 Jan 1994 02:31:31 +0200 Fraser Neiman wrote that to become accepted, a hypothesis needs to fit not only the evidence but also other theories. Indeed, this is one of the main ways how science guarantees that the views about the world that finally get accepted are coherent. We do not want to accept a bunch of hypothesis, even if each of them fits some facts, if the total picture becomes fragmented and internally inconsistent. Since all new hypothesis are evaluated against the previously accepted ones, it is very difficult to get such a hypothesis accepted that would require the modification of "what we already know". Of course this is how it should be. But scientific knowledge is not absolute, and therefore we should not categorically refuse to check on those established theories. They might benefit from being updated. As to the "functional package" explanations of human evolution, there are some crucial differences between the "hands-tools-reduced canines -brain -bipedalism" package and the packages discussed by the aquatic theory. The "hands-tools-etc." package is a very artificial one. All these traits are considered as important changes towards hominization, but that is the main reason why people started to consider them together. Because this combination of traits is not found among other animals, we do not know if it actually is a functional package or not. The aquatic theory lumps traits into a package on entirely different grounds, namely because of their co-occurrence in other animal species. And since these other animals are (semi)aquatic, we have some reason to believe that the package indeed is adaptational and evolved in a certain ecological situation. Consequently, the selection pressures would have acted on each of the traits separately, but simultaneously. Thermoregulation in wet conditions? Develop fat and get rid of hair. Locomotion in water? Become bipedal and develop a diving ability. Breathing in water? Avoid it, and develop concious control over breathing and a way to close the nasal passage instead. The old "hands-tools-" sequence has no such ecology to go with it. Therefore all the traits depend mainly on each other, and the evolution of new traits is explained by the existence of the old ones. The result is rather shaky, though, and the sequence of events is far from clear. Hanna Tuomisto hantuo@utu.fi _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:53>From jsutton@laurel.ocs.mq.edu.au Mon Jan 10 18:39:49 1994 Date: Tue, 11 Jan 1994 11:34:37 +1100 (EST) From: John Sutton <jsutton@laurel.ocs.mq.edu.au> Subject: Re: seeking examples of "train of thought" metaphor To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Re: John Limber's query on "trains of thought" I can't offhand think of this expression earlier than Hobbes. But one related, and less metaphorical, use was in associationist physiological psychology: "trains of motions in the animal spirits" were the mechanism by which trains of thought occurred, and could be adapted to various metaphysics of mind. This phrase was used by Locke in the ESSAY 4th edition (II.33) and parodied by Sterne: and I suspect that it was already current in C17 animal spirits theory. One implication of both metaphors with which later writers would get uneasy was that mind/brain processes may escape conscious control and exceed the ministrations of the will. John Sutton History Philosophy & Politics Macquarie Uni NSW 2109 jsutton@laurel.ocs.mq.edu.au _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:54>From SWIJTIN@ucs.indiana.edu Mon Jan 10 19:27:02 1994 Date: Mon, 10 Jan 94 20:30:23 EST From: "ZENO G. SWIJTINK" <SWIJTIN@ucs.indiana.edu> Subject: RE: seeking examples of "train of thought" metaphor To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu The Old OED gives: 1690 LOCKE Hum. Und. II, xiv par. 3. A train of Ideas, which constantly succeed one another in his Understanding. Zeno Swijtink HPSC, Indiana University swijtin@ucs.indiana.edu _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:55>From SMITGM@hawkins.clark.edu Mon Jan 10 20:10:52 1994 To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu From: "Gerard Donnelly Smith" <SMITGM@hawkins.clark.edu> Organization: Clark College, Vancouver WA, USA Date: 10 Jan 94 18:10:19 PST8PDT Subject: music and meaning Would anyone on darwin-l wish to discuss music and meaning in regards to poetics, semiotics, semantics? I've just finished John Shepherd's book MUSIC AS SOCIAL TEXT and found his theories exciting. I wrote my doctoral dissertaion, "Sound Foundations: Music, Lanauge and Poetry," exploring the connection between sound and meaning in poetry and now wish to pursue a dialog concerning the social implications of sound beginning with music as a symbolic structure. A semiotic analysis, I believe might uncover a "code" which regulates the generation of musical meaning. This "code" would have economic, cultural, metaphysical, as well as social imperatives. Let me begin with an example I recall from youth. I can't recall the exact commercial, but it involved a cold remedy. When the commercial began, the notes "Da-da-da-DA" from Beethoven's Fifth would sound. After several exposures to the combination of sound, image and text, I associated Beethoven's lietmotif with cold medicine. Dr. Gerard Donnelly-Smith e-mail: smitgm@hawkins.clark.edu English Department phone: 206-699-0478 Clark College Vancouver, WA 98663 _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:56>From WILLS@macc.wisc.edu Mon Jan 10 20:11:13 1994 Date: Mon, 10 Jan 94 20:11 CDT From: Jeffrey Wills <WILLS@macc.wisc.edu> Subject: Re: A positive and workable idea for the historical linguists To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Bob O'Hara points out an important difference between systematics and historical linguistics: >It does seem to be a difference between systematics and historical linguistics >that the linguists will sometimes claim that certain major language families >are either not historically related, or that the evidence that they are can >never be recovered. Systematists, in contrast, tend to assume that everything >is related (there is only one tree of life), and that it's just a matter of >figuring out what these historical relationships are. That being the case, >it may be difficult for some of the systematists to understand criticism of >Greenberg et al. on the grounds of non-relationship of the languages, because >it is one of the routine assumptions of our field that "non-relationship" >doesn't really exist; it's all a matter of more and less close relationship. >The geographic points (which I was quite pleased to see) also tend to run >counter to our common assumptions. This is _not_ to say that we are right >and the linguists are wrong; it is only by way of pointing out how each of our >disciplines is inclined to approach the problem. Wallace wrote a classic >paper in 1855, as he was trying to develop his ideas on evolution, in which he >proposed what is now usually called "Wallace's Law": "Every species has come >into existence coincident in both space and time with a pre-existing closely >allied species." Some comments: I think most linguists would subscribe to Wallace's Law. Our problem is that borrowing between distantly-related or "unrelated" languages can often give the illusion of close relationship (especially to those working mainly by lexical equivalences). Biologists also have the problem of convergence, but for language this seems to be a much more common phenomenon. As a result, linguists treat adjacent languages with some caution if systematic reflexes cannot be shown. The fundamental difference, as O'Hara rightly points out, is in the assumption about possible "non-relationship". Demonstrating that language A has more features in common with B than any other language doesn't necessarily do much if you are always suspecting non-relation. The comparative method in a sense relies on process of elimination (ruling out universals and borrowing) and borrowing is most easily eliminated in the case of languages which have been separated for some time. In short, Language varieties arise coincident in space and time but their genetic affiliation is most easily demonstrated when they are no longer coincident. A question: Are there major consequences from including/excluding possible "non-relationship"? What differences are created by assuming that all the jigsaw pieces on the table come from one puzzle rather than from several? Is this just a possibility in human culture systems (like the tree of writing systems or legal systems) or is non-relationship a question in other historical sciences too? Jeffrey Wills wills@macc.wisc.edu _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:57>From RSOLIE@smith.smith.edu Tue Jan 11 06:35:36 1994 Date: 11 Jan 1994 07:40:31 -0400 (EDT) From: RSOLIE@smith.smith.edu Subject: Re: music and meaning To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu And that same Beethoven motive, of course, was once associated with Victory in war because (I guess) ..._ is Morse code for "V." Ruth Solie rsolie@smith.smith.edu _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:58>From barbieri@dogon.geomin.unibo.it Tue Jan 11 07:19:43 1994 Date: Tue, 11 Jan 1994 16:37:30 +0300 To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu From: barbieri@dogon.geomin.unibo.it Subject: Re: music and meaning >And that same Beethoven motive, of course, was once associated with Victory >in war because (I guess) ..._ is Morse code for "V." > >Ruth Solie >rsolie@smith.smith.edu Wrong. The Beethoven motive was at the beginning of the BBC broadcast to the occupied territories. We, here in Italy, remember it very well. R. Barbieri Roberto Barbieri Dipartimento di Scienze Geologiche Universita' di Bologna Via Zamboni 67 40127 Bologna Italy Voice +39-51-354548 Fax +39-51-354522 Email barbieri@geomin.unibo.it _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:59>From mahaffy@dordt.edu Tue Jan 11 07:31:31 1994 Subject: Fair to Desmond & Moore? To: Address Darwin list <Darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu> Date: Tue, 11 Jan 1994 07:36:46 -0600 (CST) From: James Mahaffy <mahaffy@dordt.edu> I would like to include a reference to Desmond and Moore in a annotated bibliography I am going to hand out this semester. However, since I have only had time to read of couple of chapters and am not a historian, i would appreciate feedback on the annotation that I include below. Have I hit both the strengths and weaknesses of the book. Thanks, --- Desmond, A. and Moore, J. 1991 Darwin: The Life of a Tormented Evolutionist Warner Books, New York 808 pages, I have only read parts of this fascinating and widely acclaimed biography of Darwin but that reading and a number of reviews give me a good feeling for the book. The book, written by two leading Darwin scholars, will give you a real sense of Darwin and his time. In fact what makes the book unique is their seeing Darwin in terms of his social position, the influence of his family and the social context of the time. To show the effect of these influences and make them real (both of which they powerfully do) they write as if they knew what was influencing Darwin and going through his mind, and flush out historical details where needed. This in fact makes the book to some extent a historical fictionalized novel. Although well footnoted, sometimes I would like to have known what is fact and what is conjecture. For instance, did Grant (a teacher that influenced Darwin in his undergraduate days) actually go on walks with Darwin (it is logical - but there is is no proof in the book that their connection occurred in this manner). Still there is a mass of documented detail and their style makes Darwin and his situation live. I am sure every Dordt student would appreciate "indignation" at a friend being confined to the college for the rest of the semester because he fell asleep on Darwin's couch after a hike in the wilds and missed curfew. This is a good biography but every biologist should still read for himself some of what Darwin wrote. Pick up and look at the book On the Origin of the Species by Means of Natural Selection from our library to feel the force of his arguments and the type of logical presentation he makes. Darwin provided a mechanism that scientists could use to explain origins with out the supernatural to a world that to a large extent was ready to explain it that way, but in the empirical sciences, he could not have changed the paradigms of his time without some force to his argument. Even those of us who walk in a different paradigm believing in a God who creates and sustains this world should still understand the present neoDarwinian theory and its historical origins. This book, Darwin, is not in library but you are more than welcome to borrow my copy. -- James F. Mahaffy e-mail: mahaffy@dordt.edu Biology Department phone: 712 722-6279 Dordt College FAX 712 722-1198 Sioux Center, Iowa 51250 _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:60>From parkerd@ucsu.Colorado.EDU Tue Jan 11 11:29:27 1994 From: PARKER DOUGLAS RAY <parkerd@ucsu.Colorado.EDU> Subject: Re: Greenberg & Renfrew (one last time) To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Date: Tue, 11 Jan 1994 10:32:48 -0700 (MST) As an archeologist who works in the state of Colorado, I must make a comment. The Athapaskan peoples on the plains were there when Coronado arrived. His exploration of the southern plains reveals that Athapaskan peoples were in Texas, New Mexico, and Oklahoma at that time 16th century. Another point, The Dismal River Culture is prehistoric Athpaskan, and they are found throughout eastern Colorado up to the 17th century. Sometime in the late 16th or early 17th is the earliest that Athpaskan speakers could have entered the Southwestern United States Region. Douglas Parker Department of Anthropology University of Colorado at Boulder PARKERD@UCSU.COLORADO.EDU _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:61>From DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Tue Jan 11 12:07:48 1994 Date: Tue, 11 Jan 1994 13:13:13 -0400 (EDT) From: DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Subject: Systematics and linguistics To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Organization: University of NC at Greensboro We seem to be having a problem with mail posted to the list from bitnet addresses. Two or three messages have been sent to the ukanaix administrator describing the problem, but I have not yet had a response. Anyone who is trying to post from a bitnet address and isn't having any luck may forward the bounced message to me (Bob O'Hara, darwin@iris.uncg.edu) and I will post it. This comes from Kent Holsinger: ---------------------------------------------------------------------------- In the course of an interesting exchange between Jeffrey Wills and Bob O'Hara about systematists and linguists attitudes about relationships, Jeffrey makes the following observation: Borrowing between distantly related or "unrelated" languages can often give the illusion of close relationship ... Biologists also have the problem of convergence, but for language this seems to be a much more common phenomenon. I think there is an important observation lurking here. The appropriate biological example is *hybridization* not *convergence*. Hybridization between species can lead to the appearance of characters in one species that were "borrowed" from another species in a way that seems exactly analogous to the way in which English "borrowed" many words from French following the Norman invasion. (I'm a biologist, not a linguist, so I may have missed something important. If so, please correct me.) Hybridization also causes problems for biological systematists. When there is hybridization, relationships cannot be expressed as a tree. They are reticulate. In sexually reproducing species, for example, it's not possible to describe the relationships among individuals in a population as a tree because the indvidual genealogies are connected in many complex ways. The reason hybridization doesn't impose an insuperable burden on biological systematists is that biological evolution is *mostly* non-reticulate once you get above the level of species. Jeffrey Wills argument would suggest that reticulation is much more prevalent in language evolution than in biological evolution, especially at higher levels. If biologists had the same degree of reticulation to worry about, I'm sure we'd have many of the same misgivings. -- Kent +--------------------------------------------------------------------+ | Kent E. Holsinger Internet: Holsinge@UConnVM.UConn.edu | | Dept. of Ecology & BITNET: Holsinge@UConnVM | | Evolutionary Biology, U-43 | | University of Connecticut | | Storrs, CT 06269-3043 | +--------------------------------------------------------------------+ _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:62>From BOTCFNR@vm.uni-c.dk Tue Jan 11 18:52:54 1994 Date: Wed, 12 Jan 94 01:11:30 DNT From: Finn Rasmussen <BOTCFNR@vm.uni-c.dk> Subject: Fantastics and parsimony To: Darwin-L@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu David K Hill wrote that it is wrong that the most parsimonious explanations are also the least fantastic. OK, - I actually mentioned the heliocentric world view as an exception. I would still think that it works as a rule of thumb. The "established scientific" explanations of various phenomena are often a good deal more parsimonius than the alternatives suggested by popu- lar fantasy writers. But it is of course difficult for the readers to decide if von Daeneken is a new Copernicus or just another crank. The reason why I think that political/religious analogy is a more dangerous source of inspiration is that it make people wish that one particular expla- ation is true, rather than just wishing to know a parsimonious explanation. May be some the historically oriented list members can explain what was at the core of the heliocentric/geocentric world view controversy. Finn Rasmussen, Botanical Lab, Copenhagen. _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:63>From sally@pogo.isp.pitt.edu Tue Jan 11 19:31:23 1994 To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Subject: Re: Systematics and linguistics Date: Tue, 11 Jan 94 20:34:44 -0500 From: Sally Thomason <sally@pogo.isp.pitt.edu> Kent Holsinger brings up the issue of frequency of hybridization in language history, as opposed to biological evolution. It's true that it's a lot easier (and more common) for languages to borrow features than for "a little" hybridization to occur in biological species (as far as I know); but hybridization to the point that the branchings in a linguistic family tree become obscured seems to be rare. That is: slight to moderate linguistic borrowing -- not just words, but also sounds, syntax, and even some word structure -- doesn't obliterate the main lines of descent of a language; and when borrowing becomes so extreme that the main lines of descent are seriously obscured, there are usually clues in the structure of the language. Most often, the vocabulary doesn't match the grammar, in a seriously mixed language -- that is, the vocabulary and grammar can't both be traced to the same historical source. In my view, when this happens you can't put the mixed language in a family tree at all, and it isn't related (in the sense of descent with modification) to any of its source languages. The best-known examples are pidgin and creole languages, like Tok Pisin (a.k.a. Melanesian Pidgin English), whose vocabulary comes almost entirely from English but whose grammar can't be traced to English at all. Other striking examples are mixed languages like Michif, whose noun phrases are French and whose verb phrases (and most of the syntax) are Cree (an Algonquian language, Canada). So I don't think reticulation, to use the biological terminology Kent Holsinger was using, is too likely to be a stumbling block -- at least not often -- in the effort to establish relationships among languages. As in biology, linguistic evolution is, as far as I can tell, mostly non-reticulate...as long as you're dealing with completely separate languages and not dialects of the same language, and as long as you are looking at languages as wholes rather than at individual linguistic features taken separately. Sally Thomason sally@pogo.isp.pitt.edu _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:64>From sctlowe@kraken.itc.gu.edu.au Wed Jan 12 00:04:53 1994 Date: Wed, 12 Jan 1994 16:01:28 +1000 (EST) From: Ian Lowe <I.Lowe@sct.gu.edu.au> Subject: Beethoven's 5th and the BBC To: Darwin-L@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu My memory is that Roberto Barbieri, who pointed out that the opening notes of Beethoven's 5th Symphony opened BBC news broadcasts during World War II, and Ruth Solie, who noted that three dots and a dash are Morse code for V [for victory], are both right. In other words, the music was chosen to open the news broadcasts because of the happy coincidence with the Morse code symbol for the letter V. The motif became a symbol of resistance - and one it was impossible to suppress, being the work of a great German composer! I confess to having been quite young at the time, but I read that explanation in the 1940s... Ian Lowe [neither a musicologist nor an expert in codes!] _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:65>From DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Wed Jan 12 17:41:59 1994 Date: Wed, 12 Jan 1994 18:47:58 -0500 (EST) From: DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Subject: Status of anti-neo-Darwinism? To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Organization: University of NC at Greensboro The following comes from John Wilkins, who was having trouble posting it from his site. -- Bob O'Hara (darwin@iris.uncg.edu) -------------------------------------------------------------------------- I recently read _Evolution as entropy_ by Brooks and Wiley (second edition 1988). As much as my abysmal lack of math will permit, I understand that they are making a fairly strong non-neo-Darwinian claim: to wit, that selection is not the most important factor in directional change; but instead that the possibility spaces created by the present configuration of a system (organism, species, population, ecology) constrains the direction in which that system may develop. This is overtly orthogenetic, although not neo-Lamarkian in the sense that there is no anticipatory mechanism for variation. Not being a biologist, I am interested to hear from them what the status of these views is, whether the strong selectionist program is now withering or if we now have two strong competitors for evolutionary explanation. Cheers John Wilkins - Manager, Publishing, Monash University, Wellington Road, Clayton, Victoria 3168 [Melbourne] Australia Internet: john.wilkins@udev.monash.edu.au Tel: (+613) 905 6009; fax: 905 6029 ******* Monash neither knows, nor approves, of what I say _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:66>From DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Wed Jan 12 18:07:13 1994 Date: Wed, 12 Jan 1994 19:13:03 -0500 (EST) From: DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Subject: January 12 -- Today in the Historical Sciences To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Organization: University of NC at Greensboro JANUARY 12 -- TODAY IN THE HISTORICAL SCIENCES 1778: WILLIAM HERBERT is born at Highclere, Hampshire, England. A junior member of an aristocratic family, Herbert will study at Eton and Oxford, and then take a seat in the House of Commons. Leaving politics for the ministry in 1814, Herbert will move to the parish of Spofforth in Yorkshire, where he will remain for the rest of his life. An interest in botany will lead Herbert to become a skilled horticulturalist, and his extensive studies of plant hybrids will form the basis of part of Darwin's discussion of hybridism and sterility in the _Origin of Species_ (1859). Today in the Historical Sciences is a feature of Darwin-L, an international network discussion group on the history and theory of the historical sciences. For more information about Darwin-L send the two-word message INFO DARWIN-L to listserv@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu, or gopher to rjohara.uncg.edu (152.13.44.19). _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:67>From DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Wed Jan 12 22:43:49 1994 Date: Wed, 12 Jan 1994 23:49:40 -0500 (EST) From: DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Subject: Re: Status of anti-neo-Darwinism? To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Organization: University of NC at Greensboro It's been a while since I've looked at the Brooks and Wiley work on evolution and entropy, but I just wanted to put in my two cents on John Wilkins's more general question about the status of "neodarwinism." "Neodarwinism" refers to the general understanding of the evolutionary process that developed first in the period of the "Modern Synthesis" of the 1930s and 1940s. A tiny sketch of the relevant history would go like this: after 1859 most people accepted the theory of descent but relatively few accepted natural selection as the mechanism of evolutionary change; fewer and fewer as we approach 1900. By 1900 natural selection was very unpopular but descent was universally accepted. Round about the 1930s a number of lines of evidence converged from genetics, biogeography, and population systematics that caused natural selection to be accepted as the principal mechanism of evolutionary change once again. This convergence of a variety of lines of evidence was called the "Modern Synthesis", and it is usually associated with the work of people like Mayr, Dobzhansky, Wright, Fisher, Haldane, Simpson, Stebbins, and many others. "Neodarwinism" is the term that is usually applied to the views of this period: "darwinism" because it represented a revival of natural selection as the principal mechanism of change, and "neo" because it did replace or discard certain elements of Darwin's own views, most notably Darwin's belief in "soft inheritance" (Lamarckian inheritance). In the last ten or twenty years, however, a number of people who have made an assortment of discoveries have declared as a result of their work that "neodarwinism is dead!" The problem with this is that neodarwinism isn't some singular proposition that can be declared true or false; it's a whole constellation of work that includes most of 20th-century population genetics, the rejection of soft ("Lamarckian") inheritance, the notion that speciation usually requires geographical isolation (allopatry), the adoption of "population thinking" and the rejection of essentialism, and on and on. The claim that neodarwinism has been proven false is somewhat like saying: "Senator X was elected by a majority of the people in his state, but we have proof that Senator X is an embezzeler. Thus democracy is a complete failure as a system of government, because embezzelers are elected to office under democracy." "Ah, but the fact that the third position in a DNA codon can drift randomly and is not subject to selection destroys the whole neodarwinian edifice!" I don't see how such a claim can be defended when in the very paragraph in the _Origin_ where Darwin defines natural selection he speaks of variations which are neither useful nor injurious remaining as a fluctuating element within any population. "Ah, but some speciation is not allopatric!" Of course. Is that a death-blow to the modern synthetic theory of evolution? Hardly. "Ah, but what about punctuated equilibrium!" A "minor gloss on neodarwinism" as someone recently said. "Ah, but organismal variation is constrained within certain limits; organisms don't vary equally in all directions and so can't be molded like clay!" Yes, that's right. Did anybody ever really believe otherwise? (If anybody did believe otherwise, well, I'm sure the Synthesis folks got a few things wrong here and there, like we all do. No big deal.) Now, are there specific and interesting questions that can be asked about any of these particular points? Absolutely. Just what conditions must be met for sympatric speciation to occur? What is the nature of the the constraints on variation and how do they themselves vary across taxa and through time? How important is random drift in populations of different structures and sizes? All of these are very interesting and valuable questions one may ask. But each one of these questions must be framed in a very specific manner. For a really good example of interesting questions within the neodarwinian framework take a look at George C. Williams new book _Natural Selection_ (Oxford Univ. Press, 1992). I think Williams's discussion of the notion that particular taxa have their variation constrained by "bauplans" is particularly good. Some time last semester _Time_ magazine had a cover story about dinosaurs with the bold headline "Dinosaurs: Everything you know about them is wrong!" One of my students looked at me with a sort of worried look when he saw it and said "Everything I know is wrong?" I told him not to worry; it's how they sell magazines. I guess I feel the same way about "Neodarwinism is dead!": it's an eye-catcher for sure, but by itself I'm not sure it's a whole lot more. Bob O'Hara, Darwin-L list owner Robert J. O'Hara (darwin@iris.uncg.edu) Center for Critical Inquiry and Department of Biology 100 Foust Building, University of North Carolina at Greensboro Greensboro, North Carolina 27412 U.S.A. _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:68>From DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Thu Jan 13 00:06:28 1994 Date: Thu, 13 Jan 1994 01:12:23 -0500 (EST) From: DARWIN@iris.uncg.edu Subject: January 13 -- Today in the Historical Sciences To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Organization: University of NC at Greensboro JANUARY 13 -- TODAY IN THE HISTORICAL SCIENCES 1794 (200 years ago today): PROSPER GARNOT is born at Brest, France. As an assistant surgeon in the French navy, Garnot will sail under Duperrey on the _Coquille_ during its circumnavigation of the globe (1822-1825). In the company of the naturalist Rene-Primevere Lesson, Garnot will collect extensively along the coasts of South America and in the Pacific, although many of his specimens will be lost in a shipwreck in July of 1824. With Lesson he will author the zoological section of the voyage's report, _Voyage autour du monde execute par order du roi sur la corvette La Coquille pendant les annees 1822-1825_, which will be published in Paris between 1828 and 1832. Today in the Historical Sciences is a feature of Darwin-L, an international network discussion group on the history and theory of the historical sciences. For more information about Darwin-L send the two-word message INFO DARWIN-L to listserv@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu, or gopher to rjohara.uncg.edu (152.13.44.19). _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:69>From ronald@uhunix.uhcc.Hawaii.Edu Thu Jan 13 02:32:42 1994 Date: Wed, 12 Jan 94 22:36:00 HST From: Ron Amundson <ronald@uhunix.uhcc.Hawaii.Edu> To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu Subject: On critiques of "neoDarwinism" I shudder to question the opinions of our fearless leader in this enterprise, but I think Bob O'Hara's appraisal of the criticisms of neoDarwinism is too defensive. There are indeed serious critics of mainstream post-Synthesis evolutionary biology, and they're not just out to gather Time magazine headlines -- in fact most of them get no press at all. This is not to say that science reportage on the issues is _conscientious_... reporters are after sexy stories, after all. But there are critics of varying degrees of contentiousness who claim that mainstream evolutionary studies have systematically ignored certain important topics of study. The Brooks and Wiley self-organizing-systems approach is one avenue of criticism; another (my favorite) is the underrepresentation of embryological and developmental-biological knowledge in mainstream evolutionary studies. I'm reluctant to start email debates on the subject in Darwin-L, both because I'm involved in plenty of them outside of Darwin-L, and also because D-L is too important a forum to be clogged with debates of this complexity. But I will gather an annotated bibliography of (what I see to be) the important developmentalist literature critical of current mainstream evolution theory, and post it to D-L. And I'll ( at that time) invite any real masochists to read a couple of my own recent ramblings on the topics. BTW, "orthogenetic" is a very misleading term to apply to the Brooks and Wiley approach -- even if they do use it themselves. Reduced ranges of variation and biased probabilities of certain trajectories is not very similar to what the great 19th c. orthogeneticists meant by the term. Finally, in the true historical spirit of Darwin-L, I will note that the term "neoDarwinism" originally referred to Weismann's version of Darwinism, which did indeed distinguish germ line from soma line cells, and so rule out use-inheritance. But that was all 50 years or so before the Synthesis. It is, of course, appropriate and customary to refer to the results of the Modern Synthesis as "NeoDarwinism". I mean, hell, they're our words, aren't they? (Linguists may have views on that bit of armchair arrogance.) Cheers, Ron Amundson Univ. of Hawaii at Hilo ronald@uhunix.uhcc.hawaii.edu ronald@uhunix.bitnet _______________________________________________________________________________ <5:70>From ARKEO4@FENNEL.WT.UWA.EDU.AU Thu Jan 13 03:32:43 1994 Date: Thu, 13 Jan 1994 17:37:39 +0800 (SST) From: ARKEO4@FENNEL.WT.UWA.EDU.AU Subject: RE: On critiques of "neoDarwinism" To: darwin-l@ukanaix.cc.ukans.edu On: > Date: Thu, 13 Jan 1994 02:40:08 -0600 > From: Ron Amundson <ronald@uhunix.uhcc.Hawaii.Edu> noted, very much in passing, > Finally, in the true historical spirit of Darwin-L, I will note that > the term "neoDarwinism" originally referred to Weismann's version of > Darwinism, which did indeed distinguish germ line from soma line > cells, and so rule out use-inheritance. which of course is relevant, pretty much, only to ONE of the 4/5/6/? [take your pick] Kingdoms. I wonder how much this old, and only occasionally relevant, idea about the nature of genetics and hereditability has affected all of our ideas about the "fundamental" nature of evolutionary processes? Dave Rindos, back thinking about somatic selection . . . which might well be relevant to the recent fascinating discussion on the nature of linguistic change, and even the original post which prompted the reply quoted above. _______________________________________________________________________________ Darwin-L Message Log 5: 41-70 -- January 1994 End